+ All Categories
Home > Documents > Rethinking the principle of (sovereign) equality as a standard of civilisation

Rethinking the principle of (sovereign) equality as a standard of civilisation

Date post: 25-Apr-2023
Category:
Upload: vu-nl
View: 0 times
Download: 0 times
Share this document with a friend
22
Rethinking the Principle of (Sovereign) Equality as a Standard of Civilisation Tanja E. Aalberts VU university, Amsterdam Published in: Millennium, 42(3), 2014, pp. 767789 doi: 10.1177/0305829814543731 http://mil.sagepub.com/content/42/3/767.abstract Abstract The standard of civilisation is most often identified as the infamous legal doctrine that legitimised imperialist rule and the exclusion of nonEuropean nonChristian states from the international society. In disciplinary narratives of both IR and IL this colonial project is usually presented as a mere interlude on the way to a mature and inclusive international society based sovereign equality as its organising principle. In line with more critical historiography, which shows how colonialism is the condition of possibility for both sovereignty and international law, this article investigates how a standard of civilisation is inherent in political legal practices of international ordering. Moreover, while usually presented as a practice of exclusion, this article will analyse the more intricate dynamic of in and exclusion as basis for international order by addressing the legal politics of subjecthood (as objects and subjects of the imagined global regime). More specifically, it will address how law operates as a technology through the interplay between a standard of civilisation, the principle of equality and legal subjectivity. The article will look into legal practices of different historical periods (in the age of discovery, during the colonial expansion, and in modern international society) to analyse the workings and transformations of these legal technologies. Together this will show how an (implicit) standard of civilisation is entrenched in the operation of law as a technology of international order. This does not stop with the universalisation of sovereign equality as the organizing principle of an inclusive or ‘global’ international society. This article will argue that this reveals the productive power of law which functions not just as a juridical rule to regulate relations between independent and equal sovereign subjects, but operates as norm to produce appropriate sovereigns as members of the international society. Keywords standard of civilisation, politics of international law, equality, sovereignty, governmentality, imperialism, liberal internationalism Corresponding author: Tanja E. Aalberts, Centre for the Politics of Transnational Law, VU university, Amsterdam, De Boelelaan 1105, 1081 HV, Amsterdam, The Netherlands. Email: [email protected]
Transcript

 

 

Rethinking  the  Principle  of    (Sovereign)  Equality  as  a    Standard  of  Civilisation    

Tanja  E.  Aalberts  VU  university,  Amsterdam  

 

Published  in:  Millennium,  42(3),  2014,  pp.  767-­‐789    doi:  10.1177/0305829814543731  http://mil.sagepub.com/content/42/3/767.abstract        Abstract    The   standard   of   civilisation   is   most   often   identified   as   the   infamous   legal   doctrine   that   legitimised  imperialist  rule  and  the  exclusion  of  non-­‐European  non-­‐Christian  states  from  the  international  society.  In  disciplinary  narratives  of  both  IR  and  IL  this  colonial  project  is  usually  presented  as  a  mere  interlude  on  the   way   to   a   mature   and   inclusive   international   society   based   sovereign   equality   as   its   organising  principle.   In   line   with   more   critical   historiography,   which   shows   how   colonialism   is   the   condition   of  possibility   for   both   sovereignty   and   international   law,   this   article   investigates   how   a   standard   of  civilisation   is   inherent   in   political   legal   practices   of   international   ordering.   Moreover,   while   usually  presented   as   a   practice   of   exclusion,   this   article   will   analyse   the   more   intricate   dynamic   of   in-­‐   and  exclusion  as  basis  for  international  order  by  addressing  the  legal  politics  of  subjecthood  (as  objects  and  subjects   of   the   imagined   global   regime).   More   specifically,   it   will   address   how   law   operates   as   a  technology  through  the   interplay  between  a  standard  of  civilisation,  the  principle  of  equality  and  legal  subjectivity.   The   article   will   look   into   legal   practices   of   different   historical   periods   (in   the   age   of  discovery,  during  the  colonial  expansion,  and   in  modern   international  society)  to  analyse  the  workings  and  transformations  of   these   legal   technologies.  Together   this  will   show  how  an   (implicit)   standard  of  civilisation   is  entrenched   in   the  operation  of   law  as  a   technology  of   international  order.  This  does  not  stop  with  the  universalisation  of  sovereign  equality  as  the  organizing  principle  of  an  inclusive  or  ‘global’  international  society.  This  article  will  argue  that  this  reveals  the  productive  power  of  law  which  functions  not  just  as  a  juridical  rule  to  regulate  relations  between  independent  and  equal  sovereign  subjects,  but  operates  as  norm  to  produce  appropriate  sovereigns  as  members  of  the  international  society.    

Keywords  standard  of  civilisation,  politics  of  international  law,  equality,  sovereignty,  governmentality,  imperialism,  liberal  internationalism      

Corresponding  author:  Tanja  E.  Aalberts,  Centre  for  the  Politics  of  Transnational  Law,  VU  university,  Amsterdam,  De  Boelelaan  1105,  1081  HV,  Amsterdam,  The  Netherlands.  Email:  [email protected]  

   

 

Introduction  

Disciplinary   narratives   in   International   Relations   traditionally   situate   the   globalisation   of  international   society   with   the   post-­‐WWII   transfer   of   sovereignty   to   former   colonies   and   the  expulsion   of   non-­‐sovereign   categories   from   the   international   plane.   Legal   discourse   rather  locates   the   expansion   of   international   society   a   century   earlier,   when   international   law  was  sought   to   regulate   the   imperialist  encounters  and  colonies  were   incorporated  as  objects  of  a  global  legal  regime.  While  focusing  on  different  periods,  both  narratives  rely  on  an  evolutionary  perspective,  in  which  international  law  figures  as  both  symptom  and  cause  of  the  evolution  of  international  society,1  as  it  moves  from  an  exclusive  European  club  to  an  inclusive  community  of  sovereign  states.   In  this  progressive  narrative,   the  colonial  period  was  a  mere   interlude  on  the  way  to  a  mature  international  society,  from  1648  to  1945  (if  we  take  the  founding  of  UN  as  symbolic  for  its  maturation),  or  the  1960s  (the  big  wave  of  decolonisation).2  

This  perspective  on  the  development  of  international  law  has  been  forcefully  countered  by  recent  historiography  that  inter  alia  shows  how  colonialism  was  the  condition  of  possibility  for  the  development  of  both  sovereignty  and   international   law  as   institutions  of   international  society.3  Vice  versa,  nineteenth-­‐century  positivist  international  law  was  at  once  instrumental  in  governing   international   society.     Moreover,   the   global   realm   as   something   to   be   governed  existed   before   the   emergence   of   modern   international   society,   as   a   community   between  sovereign   states.   This   transpires   very   clearly   from   the   work   of   Francisco   de   Vitoria,   who   is  usually  conceived  as  one  of  the  founding  fathers  of  international  law.  His  most  important  work,  De  Indes  Novieter  Inventis  [1557/1917],  is  a  lecture  on  the  perennial  question  of  how  to  govern  relations  and  intercourse  between  different  communities.  While  not  yet  an  international  issue  in  conventional  modern  terms,  writing  in  the  age  of  discovery  this  became  a  pressing  question  as  the  Europeans  were  confronting  non-­‐European  communities  in  their  expeditions  across  the  globe.    

       

                                                                                                                         1  Casper  Sylvest,  '"Our  Passion  for  Legality":  International  Law  and  Imperialism  in  Late  Nineteenth-­‐Century  Britain',  Review  of  International  Studies  34,  no.  3  (2008):  403-­‐423,  405  2  For  a  problematisation  of  such  benchmark  dates,  Benjamin  de  Carvalho,  Halvard    Leira  and  John  M.  Hobson,  'The  Big  Bangs  of  IR:  The  Myths  That  Your  Teachers  Still  Tell  You  about  1648  and  1919',  Millennium  39,  no.  3  (2011):  735-­‐758;  Barry  Buzan  and  George  Lawson,  'Rethinking  Benchmark  Dates  in  International  Relations',  European  Journal  of  International  Relations  20,  no.  2  (2014):  437-­‐462  3  Of  crucial  significance  are  Antony  Anghie,  Imperialism,  Sovereignty  and  the  Making  of  International  Law  (Cambridge:  Cambridge  University  Press,  2005)  and  Martti  Koskenniemi,  The  Gentle  Civilizer  of  Nations:  The  Rise  and  Fall  of  International  Law,  1870-­‐1960  (Cambridge:  Cambridge  University  Press,  2001).  Within  IR  the  role  of  international  law  in  the  (post)colonial  project  has  been  explored  by  inter  alia  Siba  N'Zatioula  Grovogui,  Sovereigns,  Quasi  Sovereigns,  and  Africans.  Race  and  Self-­‐Determination  in  International  Law  (Minneapolis:  University  of  Minnesota  Press,  1996;  Edward  Keene,  Beyond  the  Anarchical  Society.  Grotius,  Colonialism  and  Order  in  World  Politics  (Cambridge:  Cambridge  University  Press,  2002);  Paul  Keal,  European  Conquest  and  the  Rights  of  Indigenous  Peoples:  The  Moral  Backwardness  of  International  Society  (Cambridge:  Cambridge  University  Press,  2003).    

 

While   colonialism   is   usually   presented   as   a   politics   of   exclusion,   this   article   will   analyse   the  more   intricate   interplay  between   in-­‐  and  exclusion  as  basis   for   imagining  and  ordering  global  rule.  It  disrupts  the  popular  distinction  between  a  European  zone  of  law  and  an  extra-­‐legal  zone  in   the   colonies,   by   addressing   the   legal   politics   of   subjecthood   that   constituted   both   the  colonial   power   and   the   colonial   subject   within   a   global   legal   order.   As   forcefully   argued   by  Antony   Anghie,4   this   also   disrupts   the   commonplace   that   international   law   is   about   the  ‘regulation  of  relations  between  sovereign  states’.5  Moreover,  rather  than  focusing  only  on  C-­‐19th  legal  practice  as  the  age  of  (colonial)  expansion  and  globalisation  of  the  international  legal  order,  this  article  starts  with  the  premodern  conceptions  of  the  global  rule  of  law,  that  shows  a  similar  practice  of   in/exclusion.  While  grounded  in  different  doctrinal  traditions,   in  both  cases  law   functions   as   a   technology   of   government   and   power.   Its   politics   not   only   reside   in   the  instrumentalisation   of   law   by   the   powerful   in   their   imperialist   projects,   but   also   in   its  productive  power  –  law  not  merely  regulates  interactions  between  pre-­‐existing  entities,  but  at  once   creates   subjects   to   be   governed.   The   article   investigates   how   both   premodern   and  modern   legal   practice   in   this   regard   was   imagining   and   constituting   ‘the   global’as   a   legal-­‐political   space,6    as   the  condition  of  possibility   for   legitimizing   the  colonial  endeavour.  Rather  than  merely  an  imposition  of  imperial  rule  or  conquering  terra  nullius,  this  constituted  a  more  intricate   creation   of   subjectivity   and   legal   personality   of   colonial   entities,   as   objects   and  subjects  of  the  imagined  global  legal  regime.    

In  order   to  develop   this   argument,   the  article  will   first   engage  with  Vitoria’s  De   Indis,  which  is  generally  considered  to  be  the  primitive  origin  of  international  legal  scholarship.7  Then  it   will   discuss   the   politics   of   in/exclusion   during   C-­‐19th   imperialism   through   the   work   of  important  contemporary  publicists   like   John  Westlake  and  James  Lorimer.  Two  caveats  are   in  order:   first,   though   these   are   authoritative   voices   in   the   legal   debate,   it   would   be  wrong   to  conceive   legal   discourse   as   homogeneous   at   the   time.   Nevertheless,   both   perspectives   are  illustrative   of   the   politics   of   legal   subjecthood   at   the   day,   and   show   how   law   serves   as   a  governmental   technology  that  not  merely  regulates   international   intercourse  to  establish  and  manage  order,  but  to  this  end  constitutes  its  own  subjects  as  part  of  a  global  legal  order.  As  will  be  elaborated  below,  the  principle  of  (sovereign)  equality  is  a  crucial  element  of  this  practice  of  government.  But  rather  than  the  standard  and   liberal  conception  of  sovereign  equality  as  a(n  absolute)   right   that   follows   from   the   condition   of   states   as   autonomous   and   legally  independent  entities  whose  interactions  develop  into  an  international  society  and  from  whose  will   international  law  emanates,  it  will  be  argued  that  the  principle  of  (sovereign)  equality  is  a  productive  norm  in  the  project  of  mastering  and  ordering  the  globe  via  in/exclusion.  As  will  be      

                                                                                                                         4  Anghie,  Imperialism  5 As  formulated  in  the  classical  Lotus  case,  PCIJ  1927  (series  A)  No.  10  6  See  Peter  Sloterdijk,  Im  Weltinnenraum  des  Kapitals  :  für  eine  philosophische  Theorie  der  Globalisierung  (Frankfurt  am  Main:  Suhrkamp,  2004)  Jens  Bartelson,  'The  Social  Construction  of  Globality',  International  Political  Sociology  4,  (2010):  219-­‐235  R.B.J.  Walker,  After  the  Globe,  Before  the  World  (London/New  York:  Routledge,  2010)  7  David  Kennedy,  'Primitive  Legal  Scholarship',  Harvard  International  Law  Journal  27,  no.  1  (1986):  1-­‐98.  

 

discussed   in   the   third   section,   its   functioning   as   a   norm   continues   in   contemporary   inter-­‐national  society  where  in  tandem  with  the  principle  of  self-­‐determination,  the  universalisation  of  sovereign  equality  turns  into  a  norm  to  be  equally  sovereign.  As  such,  it  operates  more  as  a  (republican)  norm  than  a  (liberal)  right.  It  is  in  this  context  that  we  can  conceive  of  the  principle  of  equality  functioning  as  a  standard  of  civilisation  inherent  in  sovereignty  as  still  one  of  the  key  institutions  of  international  society.    

The  second  caveat  concerns  the  possible  impression  of  (re)producing  a  grand  historical  narrative.  This   is  not   the   intention  of   the  article.  Without  suggesting  a   linear  progression  and  continuity  in  legal  discourse  across  centuries,  we  can  recognise  how  legal  rationalities  based  on  particular  constellations  of   sovereignty,   legal   subjecthood,  and  equality   serve  as   the  basis   for  ordering  the  globe  in  different  eras,  and  moreover,  how  a  standard  of  civilisation  is  inherent  in  such  political  legal  practices  of  international  ordering.  

 The  Age  of  Discovery  

While   generally   identified   as   an   important   legal   foundation   of   international   law,   reading  De  Indis  from  a  purely  modern  legal  perspective  is  prone  to  anachronistic  misunderstanding.8  Not  only  was  its  author  a  Dominican  monk  and  a  theologist,  but  the  text  is  very  much  situated  in  the  medieval   order,   with   the   dual   authority   of   Emperor   and   Pope   on   the   one   hand,   and   a  theological   methodology   of   legal   doctrine,   inspired   by   the   writings   of   St.   Thomas   Aquinas.  Hence   the   text   is   interlarded   with   biblical   references   as   proofs   of   Vitoria’s   legal   claims.  Moreover,   it   is   inspired   by   the   spread   of   the   gospel   as   the   natural   right   of   Christians.   In  addition,  the  text  is  written  in  the  scholastic  tradition,  but  not  free  of  teleological  reasoning,  or  inconsistencies.   That   it   is   nevertheless   identified   as   one   of   the   primate   origins   of   modern  international   law,   has   amongst   other   things   to   do   with   Vitoria’s   move   beyond   medieval  perspective  of   infidelity   as   a   just   cause   for   conquest.  Moreover,   Vitoria   refutes   the  universal  authority   of   Emperor   and   Pope,   and   argues   from   the   original   emergence   of   political  communities   (or   what   he   calls   ‘perfect   communities’)9   as   natural   entities   of   the   global  community.  As  the  author  himself  explains,  the  treatise   is  occasioned  by  the  controversy  that  emerged  from  the  encounter  with  the  aborigines  of  the  New  World  ‘commonly  called  Indians  –  who  came  forty  years  ago   into  the  power  of  Spaniards,  not  having  been  previously  known  to  our  world’.10    

Vitoria   systematically  explores   the   rights  by  which   the  aborigines   came  under  Spanish  sway.  The  central  question  is  whether  the  Indian  aborigines  were  true  owners  (of  their  territory  and   other   possessions)   in   public   and   private   law   prior   to   the   Spanish   encounter.  We   do   not  need   to   go   into   the   details   of   Vitoria’s   meticulous   rejection   of   7   proposed   but   inadequate  grounds  for  appropriation.  They  refer  to  the  medieval  governmental                                                                                                                              8  Franciscus  de  Vitoria,  De  Indis  et  de  Ivre  Belli  Relectiones  (Washington,  DC:  Carnegie  Institution  of  Washington,  [1539]1917)  9  According  to  Vitoria,  “A  perfect  State  or  community  […]  is  one  which  is  complete  in  itself,  that  is,  which  is  not  a  part  of  another  community,  but  has  its  own  laws  and  its  own  council  and  its  own  magistrates”  (Vitoria,  De  Indis,  169)    10  Vitoria,  De  Indis,  116  

 

 structure,  but  Vitoria  refutes  that  Emperor  and  Pope  would  automatically  have  civil  or  temporal   power   and   dominium   over   the   whole   world,   either   on   the   basis   of   divine,  natural  or  human  law.  This  categorisation  of  law  stems  from  Thomas  Aquinas11  and  is  crucial  to  understand  both  the  puzzle  that  Vitoria  was  confronted  with  –  as  Bartelson  aptly  pinpoints:  as  a  scholastic  writer,  Vitoria  was   ‘predisposed  to   find  universality  and  sameness’,  yet  had   to  come  to  grips  with  a   ‘striking  plurality  and  otherness’  as  a  result  of   the  discovery  of   the  New  World12  –  and  his  response  to  the  legal  problem,  which  reproduces  the  divine  premises  of  the  universal  legal  order,  but  attributes  the  issue  of  ownership  to  human  law  and  the  ius  naturale  as  innate  element  of  all  humanity  irrespective  of  religion.13  

In   this   context,   Vitoria   refers   to   the   division   of   the   world   ‘after   Noah’   into   different  provinces  and  kingdoms,  who  appointed  princes  over  themselves  by  common  agreement,  the  so-­‐called  perfect  communities:   ‘Herein   it   is  manifest   that  before   the  coming  of  Christ  no  one  was  vested  with  world-­‐wide  sway  by  divine   law  and  that   the  Emperor  can  not  at   the  present  day   derive   therefrom   a   title   to   arrogate   to   himself   lordship   over   the   whole   earth,   and  consequently  not  over  the  barbarians’.14  Hence  the  refusal  of  the  aborigines  to  recognise  Papal  and/or   Imperial  power   is  no   legitimate  basis   to  make  war  or  seize   their  goods.    Neither  does  their  identification  as  infidels,  heathens,  and  sinners  prevent  true  ownership,  as  ‘God  has  given  temporal  goods  to  the  good  and  the  bad’.15  Vitoria  finally  rejects  their  resemblance  with  slaves,  infants  and  animals  as  a  justification  for  their  conquest  on  the  basis  of  a  lack  of  ownership.  

 The  determinate  prerequisite   for  ownership   is   the  capacity  of   reason,  and  this  Vitoria  distils  from  practices,  customs  and  institutions:    

 [Indians]  are  not  unsound  of  mind,  but  have,  according  to  their  kind,  the  use  of  reason.  This   is  clear,  because  there  is  a  certain  method  in  their  affairs,  for  they  have  polities  which  are  orderly  arranged  and  they  have  definite  marriages  and  magistrates,  overlords,  laws  and  workshops,  and  have   a   system   of   exchange,   all   of   which   call   for   the   use   of   reason;   they   also   have   a   kind   of  religion.  Further,  they  make  no  error  in  matters  which  are  self-­‐evident  to  others;  this  is  witness      

                                                                                                                         11  In  his  Summa  Theologica    St.  Thomas  Aquinas  presents  four  categories  of  law:  (i)  lex  aeterna  which  refers  to  Divine  Reason  as  the  source  or  foundation  of  (the  whole  community  of)  the  universe;  (ii)  divine  law,  pertaining  to  supernaturally  revealed  precepts  for  the  salvation  of  man;  (iii)  ius  naturale,  or  natural  law  as  an  innate  element  of  all  humanity  (Christian  or  not),  by  which  humankind  executes  eternal  law  through  natural  inclination;  and  (iv)  positive  law,  which  is  the  enactment  of  natural  law  principles  as  local  laws  within  societies.  It  is  through  the  local  enactments  that  plurality  emerges;  yet  as  all  particularistic  positive  law  is  founded  on  natural  law,  this  plurality  does  not  jeopardise  the  universal  and  unitary  legal  order  which  serves  the  common  good  and  ultimately  salvation  of  men,  which  are  equally  subject  to  divine  power.    12  Jens  Bartelson,  A  Genealogy  of  Sovereignty  (Cambridge:  Cambridge  University  Press,  1995),  128,  who  also  provides  an  insightful  discussion  of  how  these  different  legal  orders  are  related.    13  Vitoria,  De  Indis,  123.  See  also  Anghie,  Imperialism,  13-­‐31.  14  Vitoria,  De  Indis,  132  15  Vitoria,  De  Indis,  122  

 

to  their  use  of  reason  …  Accordingly  I  for  the  most  part  attribute  their  seeming  so  unintelligent  and  stupid  to  a  bad  and  barbarous  upbringing,  for  even  among  ourselves  we  find  many  peasants  who  differ  little  from  brutes16      

Vitoria   here   allegedly   applies   a   kind   of   premodern   standard   of   civilisation,   based   on   a  comparison  of    institutional  practices  of  different  societies.  However,  apparently  different  from  its  C-­‐19th  successor,  the  logic  is  at  first  sight  one  of  inclusion  and  sameness.  That  is  to  say:  the  aboriginal  customs  and   institutions   in  fact  are   judged  to  be  similar  enough   to  be   identified  as  political   subcommunities,   and   to   recognise   their   legal   capacity   as   members   of   the   global  community   of  mankind.  Moreover,   if   they   suffer   from   a   lack   of   knowledge,   this   is   at   least   a  vincible  ignorance.17  Vitoria  hence  concludes  that,   like  Christians,  the  aborigines  ‘undoubtedly  had  true  dominion’.18    

It   is  on   the  basis  of   these  critical   remarks  about   legitimacy  of   the  Spanish  conquest   in  the   New   World,   his   rejection   of   Christianity   as   a   universal   standard   and   legitimation   for  conquest,  and  the  identification  of  barbarians  as  reasonably  similar  and  equal  in  terms  of  their  legal  capacity  of  true  ownership  that  Vitoria  is  often  identified  as  a  kind  of  humanitarian-­‐avant-­‐la-­‐lettre.  However,   a   close   reading  of   the   third   section  of  De   Indis  makes   clear   that  both   the  conclusion   of   Vitoria’s   rejection   of   the   imperialist   project,   and   the   conclusion   that   his   work  ultimately  justifies  the  Spanish  conquest,  are  premature.19    In  this  section  Vitoria  presents  7  or  8   (he   is   unsecure   about   the   validity   of   the   last   one)   grounds   for   appropriation,   that   could  legitimise   the   Spanish   conquest.20   However,   as   this   is   written   in   a   hypothetical   modus  representative   of   the   scholastic   tradition,   it   ultimately   remains   inconclusive   about   the  legitimacy  of   the  Spanish  conquest.  What   is  of  most   interest   for   the  current  discussion   is   the  legal   framework   on   the   basis   of   which   Vitoria   argues   we   need   to   judge   the   (il)legality   or  (in)justice  of  the  conquest,  and  in  particular  how  both  the  Spaniards  and  the  Indians  figure  in  this   framework   –   how   they   are   identified   as   subjects   within   the   law   that   through   this   very  subjectivation  seeks  to  govern  them.    

In   addition   to   the   conclusions   in   the   first   section   that   the   Indian   aborigines   have  sufficient   reason,  and   legal  capacity   for  ownership,  Vitoria   identifies  Spaniards  and   the  newly  discovered   Indians  as   fellows  of  global  natural   society,  preordained   from  the  days  of  Noah   in  the   divine   world   order,   ‘when   everything   was   in   common’.21   The   aboriginal   political  communities  hence  are  incorporated  in  the  global  legal  community    

                                                                                                                         16  Vitoria,  De  Indis,  127-­‐8  17  Vitoria,  De  Indis,  140  18  Vitoria,  De  Indis,  128  19  see  also  Georg  Cavallar,  'Vitoria,  Grotius,  Pufendorf,  Wolff  and  Vattel:  Accomplices  of  European  Colonialism  and  Exploitation  or  True  Cosmopolitans?',  Journal  of  the  History  of  International  Law  10,  no.  2  (2008):  181-­‐209  20  The  seven  adequate  or  legitimate  titles  are  :  (1)  natural  society  and  fellowship;  (2)  right  to  spread  Christianity;  (3)  protection  of  converted  natives;  (4)  Christian  prince  given  by  Pope;  (5)  protection  again  tyranny  of  native  lords;  (6)  true  and  voluntary  choice;  (7)  alliance  and  friendship.  A  possible  eighth  title,  which  Vitoria  is  uncertain  about,  is  defective  intelligence  (Vitoria,  De  Indis,  151-­‐162)  21  Vitoria,  De  Indis,  151  

 

of  mankind,22  and  as  such  subject  to  ius  gentium  as  the  natural  or  positive  law  of  nations.23  This  inclusion,  however,   turns  out   to  be  a  double  edged  sword,  as   it  not  only  postulates  an  equal  right   to   particularity,   difference   and   independence   for   the   Indians,   but   also   obliges   them   to  stick  to  the  universal  rules  of  ius  gentium.  Paramount  for  the  just  co-­‐existence  of  nations  is  the  right   to   ‘travel   and  dwell’   (combined  with   the  universal   principle   to   treat   visitors  well   unless  they  misbehave)  and  the  right  to  travel,  both  dictated  by  natural  and  divine  law  and  customary  foundation  for  the  good  life  in  any  society,24  as  well  as  the  Christian  right  to  preach,  publish  and  propagate   the   Gospel.25     By   objecting   and   resisting   these   universal   rights,   the   Indians   are  violating   these  defining  principles  of   ‘natural   society  and   fellowship’   to   free   trade  and   travel,  and  do  an  injury  to  the  Spaniards,  and  as  such  their  acts  of  aggression  in  turn  would  legitimise  the  forceful  measures  by  the  Spaniards:    

 [W]hen  the  Indians  deny  the  Spaniards  their  rights  [to  trade  and  travel]  under  the  law  of  nations  they  do  them  a  wrong.  Therefore,   if   it  be  necessary,   in  order   to  preserve  their   right,   that   [the  Spaniards]  should  go  to  war,  they  may  lawfully  do  so  …  [T]hey  can  make  war  on  the  Indians,  no  longer  as  on  innocent  folk,  but  as  against  forsworn  enemies,  and  may  enforce  against  them  all  the   rights   of   war,   despoiling   them   of   their   goods,   reducing   them   to   captivity,   deposing   their  former  lords  and  setting  up  new  ones,  yet  withal  with  observance  of  proportion  as  regards  the  nature  of  the  circumstances  and  of  the  wrongs  done  to  them26      

Thus   the   inclusion   of   the   Indians   in   the   global   legal   order   of   the   ‘natural   society’   basically  legitimises   their   colonisation   in  which   they  actively  partake.  Moreover,   it   in   turn  allows   their  disciplining.   For   while   at   face   value   postulating   a   proto   liberal   pluralist   vision   on   the   co-­‐existence  of  different  communities  with  different  values,  religions  and  habits,  at  the  same  time  Vitoria  also  refers   to  an   implicit   standard  of  civilisation,  where   Indians  do  not  quite  meet   the  standard   of   a   perfect   State.27   Like   its   more   famous   nineteenth-­‐century   twin,   this   standard  officially  is  dictated  by  institutional  architecture  and  capacity      

                                                                                                                         22  Wilhelm  G.  Grewe,  The  Epochs  of  International  Law  (Berlin:  de  Gruyter,  2000),  148  23  Anghie,  Imperialism,  20  identifies  ius  gentium  as  a  form  of  natural  law,  but  in  fact  Vitoria  is  somewhat  inconsistent  with  regard  to  his  identification  of  ius  gentium  as  either  natural  or  positive  law.  See  also  Pekka  Niemelä,  'A  Cosmopolitan  World  Order?  Perspectives  on  Francisco  de  Vitoria  and  the  United  Nations',  in  Max  Planck  Yearbook  of  United  Nations  Law.  Volume  12  eds  Armin  von  Bogdandy  and  Rüdiger  Wolfrum  (Leiden:  Brill  2008),    301-­‐344,  318-­‐319  24  Here  Vitoria  refers  to  Matthew  chapter  25:  ‘I  was  a  stranger  and  ye  took  me  not  in’  as  proof  of  the  first  proposition  of  the  right  to  travel.  Moreover,  as  their  fellows  and  neighbours  in  the  natural  society,  the  barbarians  are  bound  to  love  the  Spaniards  as  themselves,  following  Matthew  chapter  22,  which  also  means  that  the  Indians  ‘may  not  causelessly  prevent  the  Spaniards  from  making  their  profit  where  this  can  be  done  without  injury  to  themselves’    (Vitoria,  De  Indis,  152-­‐3)  25  Vitoria,  De  Indis,  156    26  Vitoria,  De  Indis,  154,  155  27  Keene,  Beyond  the  Anarchical  Society  explores  these  two  contradictory  patterns  of  international  order  (tolerance  and  civilization)  through  the  work  of  Hugo  Grotius,  as  another  founding  father  of  modern  international  law.    

 

for  self-­‐government.  Here  the  metaphor  of  the  infant  comes  in  again,  this  time  in  its  paternalist  implications.   For  whereas   the  metaphor  on   the  one  hand   serves   to   reject   the  argument   that  Indians  are  not  true  owners,  as  ‘the  property  of  wards  is  not  part  of  the  guardian’s  property’,  it  does  not  mean  that   they  are  capable   to  govern   themselves,   judged  again  by   their  habits  and  practices:    

 Although  the  aborigines  in  question  are  […]  not  wholly  unintelligent,  yet  they  are  little  short  of  that  condition,  and  so  are  unfit  to  found  or  administer  a  lawful  State  up  to  the  standard  required  by  human  and  civil  claims.  Accordingly   they  have  no  proper   laws  nor  magistrates,  and  are  not  even  capable  of  controlling  their  family  affairs;  they  are  without  any  literature  or  arts,  not  only  the   liberal  arts,  but   the  mechanical  arts  also;   they  have  no  careful  agriculture  and  no  artisans;  and  they  lack  many  other  conveniences,  yea  necessaries,  of  human  life.28    

 Here  we  see  the  logic  of  Foucault’s  society  of  normalisation  at  work,  where  membership  status,  privilege  and  affiliation  based  on  similarity  and  equality  creates  or  imposes  homogeneity,  while  at   once   making   visible   ‘all   the   shading   of   individual   differences’   and   gaps   ready   to   be  managed.29  In  the  other  words,  the  Indian  practices  are  similar  enough  to  disclose  their  reason  and   include   them   as   equal   members   in   the   orbit   of   the   universal   legal   order,   yet   this   also  discloses   that   as   its   subjects   they   do   not   quite  meet   the   standards   of   the   lawful   (Christian)  state,  which   is   universalised   into   a  model   for   perfect   communities   under   ius   gentium.30   This  intricate  play  of   inclusion,  universalism,  equality  on  the  one  hand,  and  exclusion,  particularity  and  difference  on  the  other,  then  is  translated  into  a  responsibility  for  the  Spaniards,  that  bears  striking  resemblances  to  the  later  sacred  trust  of  civilisation:    

It  might,   therefore,  be  maintained   that   in   [the   Indian]   interests   the   sovereigns  of   Spain  might  undertake  the  administration  of  their  country,  […]  [I]f  they  are  all  wanting  in  intelligence,  there  is  no  doubt  that  this  would  not  only  be  permissible,  but  also  a  highly  proper,  course  to  take;  nay,  our  sovereigns  would  be  bound  to  take  it,  just  as  if  the  natives  were  infants.  The  same  principle  seems  to  apply  here  to  them  as  to  people  of  defective  intelligence;  and  indeed  they  are  no  whit  or   little  better  than  such  so  far  as  self-­‐government   is  concerned,  or  even  than  the  wild  beasts,  for  their  food  is  not  more  pleasant  and  hardly  better  than  that  of  beasts.      

                                                                                                                         28  Vitoria,  De  Indis,  160-­‐1  29  ‘Within  such  a  society,  membership  status,  privilege  and  affiliation  is  supplemented  by  a  whole  range  of  degrees  of  normality  ..  In  a  sense,  the  power  of  normalization  imposes  homogeneity;  but  it  individualizes  by  making  it  possible  to  measure  gaps,  to  determine  levels,  to  fix  specialties  and  to  render  the  differences  useful  by  fitting  them  one  to  another.  It  is  easy  to  understand  how  the  power  of  the  norm  functions  within  a  system  of  formal  equality,  since  within  a  homogeneity  that  is  the  rule,  the  norm  introduces,  as  a  useful  imperative  and  as  a  result  of  measurement,  all  the  shading  of  individual  differences.’  (Michel  Foucault,  Discipline  and  Punish:  The  Birth  of  a  Prison  (London:  Allen  Lane,  1977),  184).  In  his  later  lectures,  Foucault  prefers  to  talk  about  normation,  rather  than  normalisation  to  emphasise  the  primary  and  foundational  character  of  the  norm  as  basis  to  distinguish  the  abnormal  from  the  normal  (Michel  Foucault,  Security,  Territory,  Population.  Lectures  at  the  Collège  de  France,  1977-­‐78  (Houndmills:  Palgrave  Macmillan,  2007  [1978]),  56-­‐7)  30  Anghie,  Imperialism,  22-­‐23.  Says  Vitoria  (De  Indis,  169):  ‘[T]hat  is  imperfect  in  which  there  is  something  wanting’    

 

[…]  Let  this,  however,  […]  be  put  forward  without  dogmatism  and  subject  also  to  the  limitation  that  any  such  interposition  be  for  the  welfare  and  in  the  interests  of  the  Indians  and  not  merely  for  the  profit  of  the  Spaniards.31    

 Protection   and   guardianship   of   the   Spaniards   in   this   regard   are   presented   as   possible   lawful  title   under   which   Indians   have   come   under   the   Spanish   sway,   in   addition   to   the   Indians  violation  of  the  rules  of  the  global  international  legal  community  of  mankind,  and  the  waging  of  war  as  strategies  to  transform  and  discipline  the  Indians  into  a  more  perfect  community  still.32    European  expansion  

As  aforementioned,   legal  discourse  generally   locates   the  expansion  of   international  society   in  the  nineteenth  century,  when  international  law  was  transported  to  the  non-­‐European  context  in  order  to  regulate  the  imperialist  encounters  and  colonies  were  incorporated  as  objects  of  the  European  legal  regime.  As  opposed  to  Vitoria’s  recourse  to  natural  law  as  the  foundation  of  the  global   legal   order,   the   C-­‐19th   publicists   were   relying   on   positivist   law   to   ground   the   colonial  project.   Somewhat   paradoxically,   it   is   precisely   the   acknowledgement   of   law   as   a   human  institution  that  brought  about  the  exclusionary  legal  practice  of  a  dictated  distinction  between  civilised   and   uncivilised   nations.33   Whereas   the   premodern   jurisprudence   of   naturalism  conceived  of  law  as  eternal  norms  of  justice,  rendering  it  both  naturally,  God-­‐given,  universal,  inclusive  and  immutable,  the  shift  to  legal  positivism  led  to  a  conception  of  law  as  an  institution  of  European  states,  which  in  turn  obtained  an  absolute  and  supreme  civilised  status:    

 Once  civilisation  is  related  to  the  basic  types  of  human  association,  it  is  no  longer  necessary  to  be  content  with  the  mere  enumeration  and  description  of  a  bewildering  number  of  civilisations.  It  is  then  possible  to  evaluate  and  to  measure  individual  civilisations  in  the  light  of  a  universally  applicable  test  of  the  degree  of  civilisation  which  any  such  particular  endeavour  has  attained34      

Hence,  in  positivist  jurisprudence  ‘the  myth  of  the  state  of  nature  is  replaced  …  with  the  myth  of  a  fixed  set  of  principles  and  a  scheme  of  classifications  which  reveals  itself  to  the  scrutiny  of  the  expert  jurist  who  uses  this  scheme  to  establish  and  develop          

                                                                                                                         31  Vitoria,  De  Indis,  161  32  for  a  further  exploration  of  war  as  an  instrument  of  assimilation,  see  Anghie,  Imperialism,  23-­‐28  33  In  addition  to  this  doctrinal  shift,  Keal  identifies  developments  in  social  theory  and  international  political  economy  as  drivers  of  the  shift  in  thinking  about  legal  subjecthood  (Paul  Keal,  ''Just  Backward  Children':  International  Law  and  the  Conquest  of  Non-­‐European  Peoples',  Australian  Journal  of  International  Affairs  49,  no.  2  (1995):  191-­‐206,  201-­‐203).  See  also  Keene,  Beyond  the  Anarchical  Society.  34  Georg  Schwarzenberger,  'The  Standard  of  Civilisation  in  International  Law',  in  Current  Legal  Problems,  eds  George  W.  Keeton  and  Georg  Schwarzenberger  (London:  Stevens  &  Sons  Ltd.  1955),    212-­‐234  

 

international   law’.35   This   scheme,   or   rather   the   civilised   core   of   the   scheme,  subsequently   obtained   a   ‘natural’   status,   which   then   served   as   an   objective   and  universal  yardstick  for  the  required  degree  of  civilisation.  This  fits  with  a  second  element  of  positivism  hinted  at  by  Schwarzenberger’s  statement:  apart   from  the  conception  of  law  as  man-­‐made,  i.e.  as  a  positive  institution  based  on  the  consent  of  sovereigns,  it  is  characterised  by  the  endeavour  to  provide  a  scientific,  consistent,  and  truthful  account  as  objective  alternative  to  the  subjective  fallacies  of  naturalism.  However,  it  required  some  legal  gymnastics  to  come  to  an  internally  consistent  scheme,  which  resulted  in  the  exclusion  of  barbarian  entities  on  the  basis  of  the  Standard  of  Civilisation  as  a  legal  mechanism,  coupled  to  their   (partial)   integration   into   the   framework   of   positivist   international   law   in   its   expansion  from  a  European  to  a  global  structure.36  An  important  caveat  is  in  order,  namely  that  much  of  the   legal   colonial   project  was   focused   on   regulating   the   intra-­‐European   rivalries,   rather   than  concerned  with  legitimating  the  colonial  endeavours  vis  a  vis  its  direct  objects.  However,  rather  than   the   specific   purpose   or   addressees,  what   is   of   interest   for   the   current   discussion   is   the  legal   construction   of   sovereign   subjecthood   in   relation   to   the   principle   of   equality   and   the  standard  of  civilisation  as  practices  of  in/exclusion.     The   puzzle   that   the   nineteenth   century   publicists   faced   derived   from   the   apparent  sovereign  behaviour  of  non-­‐European  entities.  This  not  only   related  to   the  degree  of  political  organisation  of  these  aboriginal  entities,  making  it  impossible  to  consider  the  African  continent  as  terra  nullius  and  free  to  be  conquested,  but,  crucially,  also  transpired  in  practices  of  treaty  making   of   indigenous   rulers   with   European   powers   themselves.37   Within   positivist  jurisprudence,   treaty-­‐making   counts   as   a   principle   source   of   law,   based   on   the   consent   of  sovereign   states.38   Treaties   as   such  are   indicators  of   the   legal   status  of   their   signatories,   and  treaty   making   can   hence   involve   an   act   of   ‘implied   recognition’   of   an   entity’s   status   under  international  law.  Apart  from  that,  and  reasoning  the  other  way  around,  the  very  possibility  of  entering   into   a   treaty   requires   a   minimally   shared   normative   framework,   that   includes   a  conception  of  the  institution  ‘treaty’  as  a   legal   instrument  which  entails  mutual  obligations  to  signatory  parties.  The  European/  indigenous      

                                                                                                                         35  Anghie,  Imperialism,  55  36  For  a  more  elaborate  discussion  of  the  relationship  between  positivism  and  colonialism,  see  Anghie,  Imperialism,  40-­‐65  37  For  a  classic  and  comprehensive  study  of  these  practices  and  their  legal  significance,  see  Charles  Henry  Alexandrowicz,  The  European-­‐African  Confrontation.  A  Study  in  Treaty  Making  (Leiden:  A.W.  Sijthoff,  1973).  see  also  Anghie,  Imperialism,  67-­‐82.  This  has  also  informed  a  critical  intervention  into  the  English  School  ‘expansion’  thesis,  and  the  distinction  between  international  system  and  society  on  which  it  is  based.  See  Tim  Dunne  and  Richard  Little,  ‘The  International  System–  International  Society  distinction’,  in  Guide  to  the  English  School  in  International  Studies,  eds  Cornelia  Navari  and  Daniel  Green  (Wiley-­‐Blackwell  2014),  91-­‐108.  On  the  basis  of  practices  such  as  these  Keene  proposes  to  shift  the  focus  from  the  expansion  of  international  society,  to  its  stratification  as  the  master  concept  to  understand  its  historical  development.  See  Keene,  ‘The  standard  of  ‘civilisation’,  the  expansion  thesis  and  the  nineteenth-­‐century  international  social  space’  in  this  issue.  See  also  Gerry  J.  Simpson,  Great  Powers  and  Outlaw  States.  Unequal  Sovereigns  in  the  International  Legal  Order  (Cambridge:  Cambridge  University  Press,  2004).  38  art  38(1)  ICJ  Statute  

 

treaty-­‐making  is  then  hard  to  reconcile  with  a  lack  of  civilisation  of  one  of  the  partners  if  that  is  defined  in  terms  of  institutions,  as  it  is  in  the  positivist  account.  The  easy  option  out  would  have  been  to  declare  the  treaties  void,  but  this  was  hindered  by  the  fact  that  these  treaties  in  many  cases  served  as  basis  for  sovereignty  claims  of  colonial  powers  within  the  African  continent;39  a  political-­‐legal  conundrum  indeed.     There  was  no  uniform   legal   standpoint   to   solve   this  puzzle.40  A  most   radical  view  was  put  forward  by  John  Westlake,  who  was  a  key  publicist  on  the  colonial  issue  at  the  Institute  de  Droit   International,   and   was   most   explicit   in   the   denial   of   any   sovereign   or   legal   status   to  ‘natives’.  He  rejected  the  argument  of  transferred  or  derivative  sovereignty,  relinquished  on  the  basis  of  treaties,  as  sovereignty  was  a  purely  European  concept,  of  which  the  native  could  not  have  a  conception.  And  how  could  one  transfer  something  he  has  no  clue  of?41  Colonial  claims  were  original,  and  qualified  as  such  under  the  Law  of  Nations.  The  treaties  then  served  at  most  a  political  purpose,  but,   in  his  view,  had  no  legal  significance.  However,   in  diplomatic  practice  the  treaties  were  respected  as  such  amongst  the  colonial  powers  themselves.42  In  this  context  it  could   be   argued   that   rather   than   their   legal   validity   as   such,  what  mattered  was   the  mutual  recognition   of   these   claims   amongst   the   European   players,   which   rendered   them   valid   in  practice.43    

What’s  more:  In  spite  of  their  dubious  quality,  both  in  terms  of  mutual  understanding,  and   in   terms   of   the   circumstances   of   their   conclusions,   as   well   as   the   legal   controversy  surrounding   them,   the   derivative   title   and   legal   significance   of   the   treaties   was   confirmed  retrospectively   in   the  Western   Sahara   case   (1975).   This   case  dealt  with   a  Moroccan   claim   to  sovereignty  over  the  Western  Sahara,  dating  back  to  the  Spanish    

     

                                                                                                                         39  This  has  prompted  questions  regarding  whether  decolonisation  in  fact  entailed  a  recovering  of  an  original  sovereignty.  See  Charles  H.  Alexandrowicz,  'New  and  Original  States:  The  Issue  of  Reversion  to  Sovereignty',  International  Affairs  45,  no.  3  (1969):  465-­‐480  40  For  a  comprehensive  account  of  the  different  viewpoints  see  Koskenniemi,  Gentle  Civilizer,  chapter  2  and  Antony  Anghie,  'Finding  the  Peripheries:  Sovereignty  and  Colonialism  in  Nineteenth-­‐Century  International  Law',  Harvard  International  Law  Journal  40,  no.  1  (1999):  1-­‐80  41  This  is  exacerbated  by  the  fact  that  in  most  occasions  the  treaties  were  not  drafted,  but  were  standard  forms  in  the  coloniser’s  language  sent  in  from  the  metropole,  which  often  only  required  the  filling  in  of  name  and  signature  or  cross.  These  colonial  practices  further  complicate  the  proposed  revision  of  the  expansion  thesis,  as  proposed  by  Dunne  and  Little,  and  Keene  (see  footnote  37),  insofar  as  this  is  based  on  the  presumption  that  social  interaction  lies  behind  treaty  making  practices  in  general.  Keene’s  social  stratification  could  provide  a  very  useful  alternative  conceptual  framework  to  the  much  criticized  expansion  thesis,  but  the  network  analysis  would  need  to  take  the  actual  context  of  the  treaty  making  practices  into  account  –  including  not  only  the  language  and  knowledge  issue,  and  the  coercive  consent,  but  also  the  fact  that  as  an  imperialist  practice  the  treaties  with  indigenous  rulers  in  fact  served  intra-­‐European  order  between  colonial  powers.  42  Koskenniemi,  Gentle  Civilizer,  127-­‐8,  138-­‐141  identifies  an  alternative  intermediate  position,  namely  that  colonial  title  was  original  rather  than  derivative,  and  the  relevance  of  the  treaties  consisted  in  their  evidence  of  ‘the  peacefulness  of  the  possession  claimed  by  the  colonizer’.  This  latter  point  is  rather  ironic  given  the  actual  circumstances  in  which  the  treaties  often  were  drafted.    43    Henk  L.  Wesseling,  Verdeel  en  Heers.  De  Deling  van  Afrika  1880-­‐1914:  Aula,  2003),  127  

 

confiscation   versus   its   status   as   terra   nullius,   which   makes   it   available   for   occupation   and  appropriation.  In  its  advisory  opinion  the  International  Court  of  Justice  concluded  that:    

 Whatever   differences   of   opinion   there   have   been   among   jurists,   the   State   practice   of   the  relevant   period   [1884]   indicates   that   territories   inhabited   by   tribes   or   peoples   having   a   social  and  political  organization  were  not   regarded  as   terra  nullius.   It   shows   that   in   the  case  of   such  territories   the   acquisition   of   sovereignty  was   not   generally   considered   as   effected   unilaterally  through   ‘occupation’   of   terra   nullius   by   original   title   but   through   agreements   concluded  with  local  rulers.  Such  agreements  with  local  rulers,  whether  or  not  considered  as  an  actual  ‘cession’    of   the   territory,   were   regarded   as   derivative   roots   of   tile,   and   not   original   titles   obtained   by  occupation  of  terra  nullius.44  

 But  where  does  this  leave  the  uncivilised  native  rulers  as  signatory  parties  to  alleged  treaties  of  cessions?  The  ambiguity  is  nicely  captured  by  Oppenheim  in  his  observation  that  

 [C]ession  of  territory  made  to  a  member  of  the  family  of  nations  by  a  State  as  yet  outside  that  family  is  real  cession  and  a  concern  of  the  Law  of  Nations,  since  such  State  becomes  through  the  treaty  of  cession  in  some  respects  a  member  of  that  family.  …  No  other  explanation  of  these  and  similar  facts  [such  as  that  these  non-­‐sovereign  entities  engaged  in  sovereign  behaviour]  can  be  given   except   that   these   [non-­‐European]   not-­‐full   Sovereign   States   are   in   some  way  or   another  International  Persons  and  subjects  of  International  Law45    

 Hence,   in   the   scheme   of   argumentation   that   appears   to   reflect   contemporary   practice  most  closely,   non-­‐European   states   were   first   acknowledged   to   be   more   or   less,   or   partially,  sovereign.   In   any   case   sovereign   enough   to   enable   in   turn   the   transferral   of   both   rights   and  status—to  dispose  of   themselves46—as  matter  of  exercising   this  partial   sovereignty.  After  all,  the  right  to  enter   into   international  treaties—including  ones  that  restrict  sovereign  power—is  an  attribute  of  state  sovereignty.47  Subsequently,  sovereignty  was  defined  in  terms  of  its  origin  as  a  European  institution,  a   ‘gift  of  civilisation’,48  which  hence  by  definition  did  not  and  could  not  apply  to  uncivilised  nations.  In  the  final  analysis  then,  barbarian  entities  were  lacking  both  sovereignty   rights   and   full   legal   personality   because   they  were   excluded   from—or   positively  formulated:   not   yet   recognised   as   members   of—the   Family   of   Nations.   By   adhering   to   the  constitutive  doctrine  of  statehood,  such  status  was  conditional  to  participation  in  the  Family  of  Nations,  and  such  admission  in  turn  depended  on  the  exclusive  discretionary  act  of  recognition  by  established  members  of  that  Family,  and  application  of  the  notorious  Standard  of  Civilisation  (SoC).  While  sovereign  statehood  was  conceived  a  natural  condition  of  European  entities,   the  origins   of   which   are   ‘beyond   history   and   inquiry’,49   in   the   case   of   non-­‐European   entities  

                                                                                                                         44  Western  Sahara  Case,  Advisory  Opinion,  ICJ  Reports,  1975,  para  80  45  Lassa  Oppenheim,  International  Law:  A  Treatise.  Volume  I  (London:  Longmans,  Green  and  co.,  1912),  86,  110    46  Grovogui,  Sovereigns,  Quasi  Sovereigns,  and  Africans.  Race  and  Self-­‐Determination  in  International  Law,  79  47  S.S.  Wimbledon  case,  PCIJ  Series  A,  No.1  (1923),  25  48  Koskenniemi,  Gentle  Civilizer,  86,  110  49  Anghie,  Imperialism,  102  

 

international   personality   and   sovereign   statehood   were   not   to   be   presumed   but   had   to   be  endowed.  This   resulted   in  the  dubious  consequence  of   the  constitutive  doctrine,  namely  that  the  European  powers  were  the  judges  in  their  own  colonial  cases.50  

When  Anghie   rhetorically  wonders  what   the   commonplace   ‘international   law   governs  sovereign  states’  means  when  non-­‐European  communities  were  denied  that  status,51  this  very  practice   reveals  how   it  operates  as  a  productive  power  and  ordering  device,   that  not  merely  regulates   interactions   between   given   entities,   but   generates   its   own   subjects   and   objects.  International  law  in  this  context  operates  as  a  juridical  rule,  as  an  instrument  of  the  sovereign  power  to  say  no  and  to  exclude  on  the  basis  of  deviance  from  an  alleged  universal  and  objective  standard.52  But  this  sovereign  power  is  itself  not  a  given  or  prior  subject,  and  the  authoritative  source  of   law,   as   positivist   doctrine  would  have   it.   Rather,   as  Anghie   also   argues,   it   is   in   the  colonial   encounter   that   the   Europeans   are   produced   as   the   original   sovereign   powers   who  command  and   impose   their  universal   law  vis   a   vis   the  uncivilised,  who   in   turn   fall  within   the  orbit  of  international  law,  and  are  recognised  as  partially  or  proto-­‐sovereign  for  the  purpose  of  their  own  subjugation,  yet  are  produced  as  outlaws  that  need  to  be  disciplined  and  civilized  via  sanctions  and  coercions  at  the  same  time.53  

The   aforementioned   political-­‐legal   ambiguity   of   the   constitutive   doctrine   was   further  exacerbated   by   the   fact   that   the   discretionary   legal   powers   of   the   established   civilized   core  were  not  bound  to  any  explicit  criteria  to  define  the  standard  itself.  Whereas  Gong  summarises  a   list   of   five   requirements   that   generally   were   identified   with   the   SoC   (including   Vitoria’s  principle  of  guarantee  of  freedom  of  travel,  commerce  and  religion  of  foreigners),  it  was  a  rule  of   customary   law   that   was   quite   flexible   in   practice,   as   also   transpires   from   the   ‘subjective  requirement’   of   adherence   to   ‘accepted   norms   and   practices   of   the   “civilized”   international  society’.54     Schwarzenberger’s   characterisation   of   the   standard   as   ‘elastic   but,   nevertheless,  relatively  objective’  is  telling  in  this  context.55  The  objectivity  of  the  SoC  was  namely  based  on  the  conception  of  the  difference  between  alien  societies  to  one’s  own:  civilisation  was  ‘not  part  of  some  rigid  classification  but  a  shorthand  for  the  qualities  that  international  lawyers  valued  in  their   own   societies,   playing   upon   its   opposites:   the   uncivilized,   barbarian   and   the   savage’.56  While  mythical  and  impressionistic,  the  existence  of  a  ‘standard’  provided  its  own  legitimacy:    

   

                                                                                                                         50  Gerrit  W.  Gong,  The  Standard  of  'Civilization'  in  International  Society  (Oxford:  Clarendon  Press,  1984),  61  51  Anghie,  Imperialism,  7  52  Michel  Foucault,  The  History  of  Sexuality.  Volume  I:  An  Introduction  (New  York:  Pantheon,  1978),  135    53  This  resonates  with  Foucault’s  suggestion  to  move  from  a  theory  of  sovereignty  to  a  theory  of  dominations  which  reveals  ‘how  actual  relations  of  subjugation  manufacture  subjects’  (Michel  Foucault,  Society  Must  be  Defended.  Lectures  at  the  Collège  de  France  1975-­‐1976  (New  York:  Picador,  2003  [1976]),  45.  54  Gong,  Standard  of  'Civilization',  14-­‐5    55  Georg  Schwarzenberger,  A  Manual  of  International  Law  (Abingdon:  Professional  Books,  1976),  84  quoted  by  Gong,  Standard  of  'Civilization',  14  56  Koskenniemi,  Gentle  Civilizer,  103  

 

‘the   existence   of   a   language   of   a   standard   still   gave   the   appearance   of   fair   treatment   and  regular  administration  to  what  was  simply  a  conjectural  policy’.57       Contrary  to  a  common  refutation,  the  subjective  element  of  the  SoC  did,  however,  not  entail   the   racialisation   of   international   politics   and   law   per   se.   Originally,   the   distinction  between  civilisations  was  indeed  based  on  racial  studies.  One  of  its  most  prominent  advocates,  James  Lorimer,  famously  declared  that  ‘[n]o  modern  contribution  to  science  seems  destined  to  influence  international  politics  and  jurisprudence  to  so  great  an  extent  as  that  which  is  known  as  ethnology,  or  the  science  of  races’.58  The  knowledge  from  racial  studies  led  to  his  infamous  tripartite  categorisation  of  humanity  into  a  civilised  zone,  a  barbarous  zone  and  a  savage  zone,  that  provided  the  basis  for  the  further  development  of  the  SoC.59  However,  under  influence  of  the  legal  positivist  turn  the  focus  of  attention  –  or  at  least  the  official  discourse  –  shifted  from  racial  features  to  institutions,  as  also  follows  from  Westlake’s  formulation  that  the  ‘difference  between  civilized  and  uncivilized  man   [for   the   lawyer  consists]   in   the  presence  or  absence  of  certain  institutions’.60  Indeed,  the  fixed  hierarchy  based  on  ‘immutabilities  of  race  and  colour’  that   would   follow   from   racial   premises   in   fact   contradicts   with   the   principles   of   progress  underlying   the   civilising   mission:   ‘At   least   in   theory,   the   standard   of   “civilization”   was  colourblind.   It   discriminated   neither   in   favour   of,   nor   against,   non-­‐white,   non-­‐European  countries’.61    

This  focus  on  institutions  as  test  for  civilisation  and  hence  entitlement  to  full  recognition  as   international   person   allegedly   was   informed   by   the   commitments   of   legal   persons   under  international  law  to  protect  the  life,  liberty  and  property  of  foreigners,  as  also  transpired  from  Vitoria’s  writings.62  Apart  from  neglecting  the  colonial  expediency  of  the  standard,  such  a  focus  however  does  not  nullify   its  Eurocentric  self-­‐referentialism  as  the   institutions  were  defined   in  terms   of   their   similarity   to   European   political   infrastructure   of   the   day.63   And   whereas   in  principle   the  SoC   left   room   for   improvement   for   the  uncivilised,   at   the   same   time   the   liberal  modernisation   notion   in   combination   with   the   language   of   a   ‘standard’   entails   a   misleading  reference   to   civilisation   as   a   definite   goal   and   specific   level   to   be   reached   in   order   to  be   (or  gain)  equal(ity)  as  international  persons.  That  this  was  misleading  follows  from  the  combination  of  the  elasticity  of  the  SoC  in  relation  to  its  alleged  objectivity:    

 

                                                                                                                         57  Koskenniemi,  Gentle  Civilizer,  135,  emphasis  omitted  58  James  Lorimer,  The  Institutes  of  the  Law  of  Nations.  A  Treatise  of  the  Jural  Relations  of  Separate  Political  Communities.  Volume  II  (Edinburgh:  Blackwood,  1883),  93  59  Lorimer,  Institutes,  101  60  John  Westlake,  Chapters  on  the  Principles  of  International  Law  (Cambridge1894),  137.  On  the  basis  of  the  same  quote  Anghie,  Imperialism,  55  maintains  that  this  shift  to  the  character  of  institutions  ‘facilitated  the  racialization  of  law  by  delimiting  the  notion  of  law  to  very  specific  European  institutions’.    Colonialism  was  hence  based  on  the  racialisation  of  sovereignty  in  his  view  (Anghie,  Imperialism,  100  and  passi;  see  also  Grovogui,  Sovereigns,  Quasi  Sovereigns,  and  Africans.  Race  and  Self-­‐Determination  in  International  Law).  This  conclusion  however  seems  to  conflate  ‘race’  with  ‘culture’.    61  Gong,  Standard  of  'Civilization',  53  62  Schwarzenberger,  'Standard  of  Civilisation',  220  63  see  also  Keal,  European  Conquest  

 

 Like   Sisyphys   the   less   “civilized”   were   doomed   to   work   toward   an   equality   which   an   elastic  standard  of  “civilization”  put  forever  beyond  their  reach.  Even  to  attain  “civilized”    status  ..  was  not  necessarily  to  become  equal.  The  “civilized”  had  a  way  of  becoming  more  “civilized”  still.64    

 As   the   standard   was   derived   from   the   gap   between   civilised   and   uncivilised,   or   more  specifically,   the   differences   between   European   and   non-­‐European   societies,   there   was   no  absolute   threshold   to   be   reached.   Instead,   the   production   of   the   colonial   subject   as   proto-­‐sovereign  was   an   ongoing,   reiterative   process   and   normative   force.65  Moreover,   it   remained  dependent   upon   judgement   of   the   gap   between   the   level   of   civilisation   of   the   periphery   in  terms  of  the  core.  However,  by  definition  the  ‘other’  is  and  always  will  be  different,  and  hence  not   (as)   civil   (as)  or   like   ‘us’.   This   is  what  Anghie  has   labelled   the  dynamic  of  difference:   ‘the  endless  process  of   creating  a  gap  between   two  cultures,  demarcating  one  as   “universal”   and  civilized   and   the   other   as   “particular”   and   uncivilized,   and   seeking   to   bridge   the   gap   by  developing   techniques   to   normalize   the   aberrant   society’.66   This   then   translated   into   the  famous  ‘white  man’s  burden’,67  and  his  responsibility  to  bring  civilization  and  salvation  to  the  barbarian   and   the   savage,   by   replacing   native   institutions   by   European   sovereignty   and  guardianship.68  

While   the   imperialist  project   is   –for  obvious   reasons–  usually  depicted  as  a  project  of  exclusion  of  non-­‐European  states  from  the  Family  of  Nations  and  its  concomitant  privileges,  the  above   discussion   revealed   at   least   two   more   intricate   ways   in   which   nineteenth-­‐century  political-­‐legal   imaginaries   and   practices   subjectivated   the   indigenous   entities  within   a   global  legal   order.   As   Keene   suggests,   they   were   insiders   and   outsiders   at   the   same   time;69   or   as  argued  here,   they  became  outsiders   through  their  very  capacity  as   insiders.  On  the  one  hand  they   were   constructed   as   legal   subjects   of   the   imagined   global   legal   regime   through   the  treatymaking  practices  or  rituals  by  which  they  officially  ceded  their  ownership  (and  in  a  sense  their   sovereign   identity)   to   the  colonial  powers.  On   the  other  hand,  while  excluding   the  non-­‐European   as   equal   sovereigns   from   the   Family   of   Nations,   the   SoC   at   once   entailed   their  inclusion   as   objects   in   the   domain   of   international   law   through   the   ‘universal’   discourse   of  civilisation  and  humanitarianism.70  Hence,  rather  than  a  mere  denial  of  their  identity  (both  on  the  basis  of  their  particularity  and  their  failure  to  meet  the  universal  standard),  non-­‐European  entities  were  endowed  with  a  subjectivity  that  rendered  them  subjects  of  law  and  ‘outlaws’  at  the  same  time,  as  Oppenheim’s  remarks  also  illustrate.  And  like  the  Indians  in  Vitoria’s  treatise,  this   inclusion   into   the   system  was   a   double   edged   sword,   as   it   not   only   included   their   own  participation   in   the   legitimation   of   their   imperial   subjection,   but   also   rendered   the   SoC  

                                                                                                                         64  Gong,  Standard  of  'Civilization',  63  65  cf.  Judith  Butler,  Bodies  that  Matter.  On  the  Discursive  Limits  of  "Sex"  (New  York:  Routledge,  1993),  94-­‐5  66  Anghie,  Imperialism,  4  67  Rudyard  Kipling,  'The  White  Man's  Burden',  McClure's  Magazine  12,  (1899)  68  Koskenniemi,  Gentle  Civilizer,  130  69  Keene,  ‘The  standard  of  “civilisation”,  the  expansion  thesis  and  the  nineteenth-­‐century  international  social  space  70  Gong,  Standard  of  'Civilization',  44-­‐5;  Koskenniemi,  Gentle  Civilizer,  130,  who  refers  to  the  discourse  of  exclusion-­‐inclusion;  Anghie,  Imperialism,  238  

 

applicable,  which  exposed  the  fundamental  differences  between  the  civilised  core  and  savage  periphery,  which  in  turn  rendered  sovereignty  and  equality  beyond  the  reach  of  non-­‐European  states.      Globalisation  of  international  society  

Against  the  backdrop  of  the  age(s)  of  imperialism,  the  1960  General  Assembly  Resolution  1514  (XV)   heralds   a   new   era   in   international   relations,   which   entailed   a   de-­‐ideologisation,  homogenisation   and   equalisation   of   the   sovereignty   game.71   The   foundational   principles   of  universality   and   equality   were   translated   into   the   membership   rules   of   the   United   Nations,  which  would  be  open  to  all   ‘peace-­‐loving  states’,   regardless  of   their   internal  architecture  and  ideology.72  This  split  between  internal  and  external  sovereignty  allegedly  signified  an  important  break   from   colonial   practices.73   It   was   also   informed   by   a   shift   in   the   legal   rationality   of  equality:  whereas  in  the  heydays  of  the  imperialist  era  Lorimer  had  claimed  that  an  equal  status  requires   an   empirical   basis,74   in   the   early   twentieth   century  Oppenheim   turns   the   argument  around   and   addresses   equality   as   an   attribute   of   a   sovereign   status.75   More   specifically,  equality   before   law   is   an   invariable   attribute   of   international   legal   personality,  which   in   turn  renders  all  other  inequalities  irrelevant  from  a  legal  perspective,  as  these  are  social  or  political,  but  not   legal   facts.  This   viewpoint,  based  on  a   separation  of   substantial  or  empirical  equality  and   formal   or   legal   equality,   is   almost   directly   translated   into   the   1970   General   Assembly  Resolution  2625  (XXV)  on  Principles  of   International  Law  Concerning  Friendly  Relations,  which  emphasises   juridical  equality  of  all   states  —both  qua  membership  status  and  qua   their   rights  and  duties—  irrespective  of  their  economic,  social  and  political  differences.76      

                                                                                                                         71  Declaration  on  the  Granting  of  Independence  to  Colonial  Countries  and  Peoples,  General  Assembly  Resolution  1514  (XV),  December  14,  1960.  See  also  Simpson,  Great  Powers  and  Outlaw  States  72  article  4(1),  UN  Charter.  In  the  Admissions  case  the  ICJ  concludes  that  article  4(1)  consists  of  an  exhaustive  list  of  criteria  for  membership  (Conditions  of  Admission  of  a  State  to  Membership  in  the  United  Nations,  Advisory  Opinion,  ICJ  Reports  1948,  57).  Notorious  exemptions  to  the  new  practice  are  the  non-­‐recognition  of  Southern  Rhodesia  and  the  South  African  homelands  due  to  their  racist  regimes.  73    Jackson  in  this  regard  distinguishes  between  empirical  and  juridical  statehood,  and  positive  and  negative  sovereignty  (Robert  H.  Jackson,  Quasi-­‐States:  Sovereignty,  International  Relations  and  the  Third  World  (Cambridge:  Cambridge  University  Press,  1990)).  For  a  critical  analysis  of  his  ‘quasi-­‐statehood’  thesis  and  the  implicit  normative  scale  that  underlies  it,  see  e.g.  Roxanne  Lynn  Doty,  Imperial  Encounters:  The  Politics  of  Representation  in  North-­‐South  Relations  (London:  University  of  Minnesota  Press,  1996)  and  Tanja  E.  Aalberts,  'The  Sovereignty  Game  States  Play:  (Quasi-­‐)States  in  the  International  Order',  International  Journal  for  the  Semiotics  of  Law  17,  no.  2  (2004):  245-­‐57  74  ‘All  States  are  equally  entitled  to  be  recognized  as  States,  on  the  simple  ground  that  they  are  States;  but  all  States  are  not  entitled  to  be  recognized  as  equal  States,  simply  because  they  are  not  equal  States’  (Lorimer,  Institutes,  1884:  260).  75  ‘States  are  by  their  nature  certainly  not  equal  as  regards  power,  extent,  constitution,  and  the  like.  But  as  members  of  the  community  of  nations  they  are  equals,  whatever  differences  between  them  may  otherwise  exist.  This  is  a  consequence  of  their  sovereignty’.  Oppenheim,  International  Law:  A  Treatise.  Volume  I,  19    76  Declaration  on  Principles  of  International  Law  Concerning  Friendly  Relations  and  Co-­‐operation  among  States  in  Accordance  with  the  Charter  of  the  United  Nations,  GA  Resolution  2625  (XXV),  October  24,  1970.    

 

The  universalisation  of  the  equality  principle  as  such  symbolises  a  fundamental  reversal  of   legal  practices.   This   radical  break  with   the   colonial  practices   is   facilitated  by  a   shift  from  the  constitutive  to  the  declaratory  doctrine,  which  means  that  legal  personality  is  no   longer  dependent  upon  a   formal  act  of   recognition,  but   follows   from  the  empirical  facts  of  statehood  itself.  It  is  further  substantiated  by  the  renunciation  of  any  criteria  of  institutional  preparedness,  which  was  the  one  of  the  justificatory  logics  of  the  SoC  in  the  nineteenth  century.77  Whereas  decolonisation  on  the  one  hand  entailed  the  homogenisation  of  the   international   society   by   levelling   it   to   one   dominant   category   of   sovereign   and   equal  statehood,  on  the  other  hand  the  model  itself  allows  for  heterogeneity  as  ‘the  right  to  differ  is  now  proclaimed   as   one   of   the   attributes   inherent   in   the   very   notion   of   sovereignty’.78  Or   at  least,   such   pluralism   or   tolerance   would   follow   from   the   decoupling   of   sovereignty   to   a  particular  set  of  cultural  and  institutional  practices,  as  is  the  premise  of  the  UN  Charter  and  was  reconfirmed  in  Resolutions  1514  (XV)  and  2625  (XXV).    

However,  the  universalisation  of  sovereignty  as  the  right  to  be  different  and  equal  at  the  same  time  as  the  foundation  of  modern  international  society  is  only  part  of  the  story.  For  one  thing,  ‘peace-­‐loving’  as  a  condition  for  membership  is  vague  and  broad  enough  a  description  to  include  other  considerations  as   indicators  of  such  peace-­‐loving  character,  such  as  the  popular  links   with   democracy   in   the   liberal   international   paradigm   that   will   be   elaborated   below.  Moreover,  while   it   is  generally  accepted   that   the  constitutive  doctrine   that  was  conducive   to  the   imperialist  project  has  now  been   replaced  by  a  declaratory   conception  of   statehood,   the  ‘international   community’   still   needs   to   judge   as   to   whether   the   conditions   are   fulfilled.   As  Lauterpacht  has  pointed  out:  facts  cannot  exist  without  a  subject  to  know  it.79  But  apart  from  the  possible  continuation  of  exclusionary  practices  through  denial  of  statehood,  what  is  of  most  interest  to  our  current  discussion  is  how  the  principle  of  sovereign  equality  itself  provides  the  parameters  for  ordering  and  making  distinctions  between  states  and  disciplining  of  those  that  do  not  adhere  to  the  rules  and  norms  of  contemporary  international  society.80    

     

                                                                                                                         77  The  decoupling  of  rights  and  capabilities  is  stated  most  unequivocally  in  articles  3  and  5  of  GA  Resolution  1514  (XV),  1960:  ‘Inadequacy  of  political,  economic,  social  or  educational  preparedness  should  never  serve  as  a  pretext  for  delaying  independence’  and  ‘  Immediate  steps  shall  be  taken  …  to  transfer  all  power  to  the  peoples  of  those  territories,  without  any  conditions  or  reservations’.  This  was  a  complete  reverse  from  the  provisions  of  the  1885  Berlin  Act,  which  identified  deficiency  in  civilisation  as  the  legitimate  ground  for  colonialism.    78  Posper  Weil,  'Towards  Relative  Normativity  in  International  Law?',  American  Journal  of  International  Law  77,  no.  3  (1983):  413-­‐42,  419  79  Hersch  Lauterpacht,  Recognition  in  International  Law  (Cambridge:  The  University  Press,  1948)  80  see  also  Tanja  E.  Aalberts  and  Wouter  G.  Werner,  'Sovereignty  Beyond  Borders:  Sovereignty,  Self-­‐Defense  and  the  Disciplining  of  States',  in  Sovereignty  Games.  Instrumentalising  State  Sovereignty  in  Europe  and  Beyond,  eds  Rebecca  Adler-­‐Nissen  and  Thomas  Gammeltoft-­‐Hansen  (Houndmills:  Palgrave  2008),    129-­‐150  

 

In  addition,   there  are  persistent  calls  within   the   liberal   internationalist  paradigm  to   formalise  such  distinctions,  which  could  be  identified  as  rule  through  equality.81    

While  in  political  discourse  sovereignty  is  often  idealized  as  some  kind  of  absolute  status  of  autonomy,  freedom,  and  privilege,   in   legal  discourse  such  rights  are   invariably   linked  to  an  extensive  set  of  duties  and  responsibilities.  As  formulated  by  the  ILC:    

States  establish  themselves  as  equal  members  of  the   international  community  as  soon  as  they  achieve  an  independent  and  sovereign  existence.  If  it  is  the  prerogative  of  sovereignty  to  be  able  to  assert  its  rights,  the  counterpart  of  that  prerogative  is  the  duty  to  discharge  its  obligations.82    

 With   the   emphasis   on   duties   as   opposed   to   rights,   sovereignty   entails   a   task   to   fulfil,   rather  than   a   freedom   to   indulge.83   Crucially,   the   scope   of   sovereign   obligations   has   expanded  significantly  in  the  course  of  the  twentieth  century.  While  they  were  still  mainly  formulated  as  a  negative   duty   to   respect   each   other’s   sovereign   rights   in   the   beginning   of   the   twentieth  century,84   this   was   significantly   expanded   after   the   Second  World  War   through   notably   the  development   of   the   human   rights   regime   and   the   emergence   of   so-­‐called   erga   omnes  obligations  vis  a  vis  the  international  community  as  a  whole.85  In  other  words,  the  content  and  scope   of   sovereignty   is   set   by   the   legal   rights   and   duties   as   its   attributes.   These   in   turn   are  contingent   and   evolve   in   light   of   normative   developments   in   international   relations,86  which  raises  the  question  of  who  gets  to  identify  the  universal  norms  of  contemporary  international  society?   In   any   case,   as   international   legal   subjects,   states   not   only   are   bearers   of   power,  authority  and  sovereign  privileges,  but  are  subject  to  international  legal  protocols  and  regimes  of  knowledge  that  empower  them  as  subjects  and  structure  their  possible  field  of  action,87  as  also   transpired   from   the   discussion   above.   This   means   that   rights   are   not   just   a   privilege  granted  to  legal  subjects,  but  constitute  their  very  personality  and  enable  in  Foucaultian  terms  the   conduct   of   (their)   conduct   (governmentality).88   What   is   more,   they   further   the  

                                                                                                                         81  for  an  alternative  proposal  for  reform  of  the  international  system  based  on  a  dualistic  order  that  encompasses  both  sovereign  equality  and  human  rights,  but  seeks  to  avoid  a  new  form  of  hegemonic  international  law  and  exclusion,  see  Jean  L.  Cohen,  Globalization  and  Sovereignty.  Rethinking  Legality,  Legitimacy,  and  Constitutionalism  (Cambridge:  Cambridge  University  Press,  2012)  82  Yearbook  of  the  International  Law  Commission  1973,  II,  p.  177  83  To  illustrate,  the  1949  Draft  Declaration  on  Rights  and  Duties  of  States  by  the  International  Law  Commission  lists  4  rights  as  opposed  to  10  duties  (www.un.org/law/ilc/texts/declar.htm)  and  also  most  articles  in  the  1970  Declaration  on  Friendly  Relations  are  formulated  in  terms  of  international  obligations.  See  Aalberts  and  Werner,  'Sovereignty  Beyond  Borders'  84  Island  of  Palmas  case,  Permanent  Court  of  Arbitration  1928,  2  RIAA  829,  p.  839  85  While  there  is  not  an  exclusive  list  of  such  norms,  the  prohibition  of  genocide,  slavery,  racial  discrimination  and  aggression  are  recognized  as  examples.  See  Barcelona  Traction  case  (Second  Phase),  ICJ  Rep  1970  para  33-­‐34    86  Nationality  Decrees  in  Tunis  and  Morocco  case,  PCIJ,  Series  B,  no.  4  (1923),  p.  24  87  Michael  Dillon,  'Sovereignty  and  Governmentality:  From  the  Problematics  of  the  "New  World  Order"  to  the  Ethical  Problematic  of  the  World  Order',  Alternatives  20,  no.  3  (1995):  323-­‐368  88    Michel  Foucault,  'The  Subject  and  Power',  Critical  Inquiry  8,  no.  4  (1982):  777-­‐95  Michel  Foucault,  'Governmentality',  in  The  Foucault  Effect.  Studies  in  Governmentality,  eds  Graham  Burchell,  Colin  Gordon  and  Peter  Miller  University  of  Chicago  Press  1991),    87-­‐105.  For  a  more  elaborate  discussion,  see  Tanja  E.  Aalberts,  Constructing  Sovereignty  between  Politics  and  Law  (London:  Routledge,  2012)  

 

normalisation  of  the  members  of  society,  as  they  are  based  on  a  normative  or  moral  idea  of  what  subjects  are  supposed  to  be  by  their  ‘nature’,89  based  on  the  metavalues  of  contemporary  international  society.90  

This  also  feeds  into  Foucault’s  somewhat  cryptic  claim  that  ‘the  law  operates  more  and  more  as  a  norm’.  In  this  regard  he  sought  to  distinguish  between  different  dispositions  of  law  –  as   sovereign   command,   constraint   and   sanctions   on   the   one   hand,   and   in   its   productive  modality   as   a   regulatory   mechanism   and   technology   of   governmentality,   on   the   other.91  Crucially,  these  norms  are  not  exogenous  (derived  from  either  some  transcendental  source  like  Vitoria’s  natural  law  or  the  sovereign  command  by  European  colonial  powers),  but  emerge  from  ‘the  group’s  reference  to  itself’,  which  is  why  Ewald  identifies  them  as  ‘social  laws’.92  Norms  in  this  regard  refer  to  the  particular  society,  which  aims  to  regulate,  order  and  produce  itself  and  its  members   on   the   basis   of   equality   and   universality   through   these   very   norms.  Moreover,  these  norms  not  only  work  in  the  traditional  sense  as  rules  of  behaviour,  but  also  function  as  a  standard   of   measurement,   a   rule   of   judgement   to   distinguish   between   the   normal   and   the  abnormal,  i.e.  identify  gaps  and  manage  deviance.93    

Different   historical   variations   of   such   classifications   can   be   identified—civilized   versus  uncivilized,  advanced  versus  backward,  developed  versus  developing  (or  failed  states),94  and  in  its  most  recent  version:   liberal  versus   illiberal  or  rogue  (and  failed)  states  as  proclaimed  most  vehemently   in   the   discourse   on   the   New   or   Postmodern   World   Order   and   liberal  internationalism.   In   this   context   there   is   a   persistent   call   by   scholars   such   as   Anne-­‐Marie  Slaughter,  Michael   Reisman,  Allan  Buchanan,   John  Rawls   and   Fernando   Tesón   for   a   qualified  right   to   differ   amongst   sovereign   states   based   on   an   explicit   link   between   universal   liberal  values  and  peace  as  a  natural  order  on  the  one  hand,  and   illiberal  and   irrational  regimes  and  aggression   on   the   other.   Re-­‐emerging   in   the   context   of   the   post-­‐Cold   War   ‘end   of   history’  discourse   to   further   progress   and  peace,   the   liberal   internationalist   paradigm  materialised   in  international   politics   through   a   ‘muscular   humanitarianism’   and   a   practice   of   illegal   but  legitimate  humanitarian  interventions.  95  After  9/11  it  has  become  increasingly  securitised,  and  

                                                                                                                         89  Brent  L.  Pickett,  'Foucaultian  Rights?',  Social  Science  Journal  37,  no.  3  (2000):  403-­‐421,  405-­‐6    90  Christian  Reus-­‐Smit,  The  Moral  Purpose  of  the  State.  Culture,  Social  Identity,  and  Institutional  Rationality  in  International  Relations  (Princeton:  Princeton  University  Press,  1999)  91  For  recent  contributions  that  discuss  the  power  of  international  law  from  a  Foucaultian  perspective  see  inter  alia  Ben  Golder  and  Peter  Fitzpatrick,  Foucault's  Law:  Routledge,  2009;  Nikolas  Rajkovic,  ''Global  law'  and  governmentality:  Reconceptualizing  the  'rule  of  law'  as  rule  'through'  law',  European  Journal  of  International  Relations  18,  no.  1  (2010):  29-­‐52,  and  a  special  issue  of  the  Leiden  Journal  of  International  Law  25(3),  2012  92  François  Ewald,  'Norms,  Discipline,  and  the  Law',  Representations  30,  (1990):  138-­‐161,  159,  154-­‐5  93  Ewald,  'Norms,  Discipline,  and  the  Law;  Nikolas  Rose  and  M.  Valverde,  'Governed  by  Law?',  Social  and  Legal  Studies  7,  no.  541-­‐51  (1998)  94  Anghie,  Imperialism  discusses  these  shifts  from  colonialism  toward  neo-­‐colonial  practices  of  the  mandate  system  and  the  Bretton  Woods  institutions,  but  does  not  include  the  liberal  vs  illiberal  distinction  as  a  contemporary  practice  of  the  dynamics  of  difference.  95  Anne  Orford,  'Muscular  Humanitarianism:  Reading  the  Narratives  of  the  New  Intervention',  European  Journal  of  International  Law  10,  no.  4  (1999):  679-­‐711.  For  a  comprehensive  overview  of  liberal  internationalism,  see  Beate  Jahn,  Liberal  Internationalism.  Theory,  History,  Practice  (London:  Palgrave  Macmillan,  2013).  Bishai  explores  the  link  between  IR  liberal  internationalism  and  liberal  international  law  (Linda  S.  Bishai,  ‘Liberal  Internationalism  and  the  law  vs  libery  paradox’,  Journal  of  International  Relations  and  Development  15  (2012):  201-­‐223).  

 

the   ensuing   War   on   Terror   has   been   cast   in   terms   of   a   global   war   against   the   enemies   of  civilisation.96    

While   there  are   some  significant  differences  within   this  discourse,97   it   is  united   in   the  aim   to   redirect   the   legal   rationality   by   claiming   that   states   are   not   equal   in   their   behaviour  according  to  the  prevailing  universal  liberal  standards  of  international  society  and  hence  should  not  be   treated  as   such,  as   this   is  detrimental  not  only   to   the  well-­‐being  of   individual   citizens  (from  whose  security  the  international  community  bears  a  responsibility  to  protect),  but  also  a  vital   threat   to   international   order   and   security.   This,   however,   in   their   view  would   not   be   a  transformation   of   the   legal   order,   but   an   acknowledgement   –   at   last   –   of   the   different  behaviours  that  states  expose  in  their  foreign  relations,  and  which  are  rooted  in  their  domestic  political   regimes.98   As   has   been   pointed   out   by   others   too,99   the   logic   mirrors   that   of   the  nineteenth-­‐century  SoC,  in  that  liberal  statehood—whose  precise  content  remains  unspecified,  but  is  loosely  characterised  by  human  rights,  market  economy,  and  some  form  of  democracy—is  naturalised  as  a  positive,  objective  and  universal  standard,  a  metavalue  which  is  itself  beyond  scrutiny  but  against  which  all  other  members  of  international  society  are  measured.  In  a  telling  quote,  Slaughter  for   instance  explains  that   ‘the  classification  of  a  state  as  non-­‐liberal  rests  on  evidence  of  adherence  to  fundamentally  different  values  and  institutions  from  those  prevailing  in  liberal  states’  as  a  matter  of  fact,  yet  in  the  same  breath  suggest  that  the  line  between  liberal  and  nonliberal  states  is  drawn  on  ‘a  deep  intuition  of  similarity  and  shared  values,  on  the  one  hand,   versus   tacit   recognition   of   difference   and   alienage   on   the   other’.100   Obviously,   the  judgment  call  lies  with  the  liberal  states  themselves,  and  as  the  boundary  between  liberal  and  illiberal   statehood   is  explicitly  defined   in   terms  of  a  dynamic  of  difference,  or  what  Slaughter  calls  the  ‘principle  of  legitimate  difference’  as  Grundnorm  for  global  governance,101  this  seems  to  put  those  that  are  marked  as  illiberal  in  Sisyphus  shoes.  This  is  even  more  so  as  sovereignty  and   equality   are   separated,   and   equality   is   turned   into   a   social   fact,   but   with   legal  consequences:   it   is   the  similarly   liberal   states  who  are  equal   in   the  zone  of   law,  whereas   the  others  are  denunciated  to  a  ‘zone  of  politics’.102  

                                                                                                                         96  Mark  Neocleus,  'The  Police  of  Civilization:  The  War  on  Terror  as  Civilizing  Offensive',  International  Political  Sociology  5,  (2011):  144-­‐159  Anghie,  Imperialism,  chapter  6  97  Jahn,  Liberal  Internationalis;  Simpson,  Great  Powers  and  Outlaw  States;  Ronald  Janse,  'The  Legitimacy  of  Humanitarian  Interventions',  Leiden  Journal  of  International  Law  19,  no.  3  (2006):  669-­‐692  98  Anne-­‐Marie  Slaughter,  'International  Law  in  a  World  of  Liberal  States',  European  Journal  of  International  Law  6,  no.  4  (1995):  503-­‐538  99  e.g.  Benedict  Kingsbury,  'Sovereignty  and  Inequality',  European  Journal  of  International  Law  9,  no.  4  (1998):  599-­‐625.  Brett  Bowden,  'In  the  Name  of  Progress  and  Peace:  The  "Standard  of  Civilization"  and  the  Universalizing  Project',  Alternatives  29,  no.  1  (2004):  43-­‐68    100  Anne-­‐Marie  (Slaughter)  Burley,  'Law  Among  Liberal  States:  Liberal  Internationalism  and  the  Act  of  State  Doctrine',  Columbia  Law  Review  92,  no.  8  (1992):  1907-­‐1996,  1920-­‐21.  See  also  the  Princeton  Project  that  linked  the  academic  debates  to  a  concrete  masterplan  to  bifurcate  the  international  order  by  creating  a  Concert  of  Democracies  G.  John  Ikenberry  and  Anne-­‐Marie  Slaughter,  'Forging  a  World  Of  Liberty  Under  Law.  U.S.  National  Security  in  the  21st  Century  (Final  Report  of    the  Princeton  Project  on  National  Security)',  The  Woodrow  Wilson  School  of  Public  and  International  Affairs,  Princeton  University,  available    101  Anne-­‐Marie  Slaughter,  A  New  World  Order  (Princeton  University  Press,  2005),  247-­‐250  102  (Slaughter)  Burley,  ‘Law  Among  Liberal  States’,  1917-­‐21;  Robert  Cooper,  The  Post-­‐Modern  State  and  World  Order  (London:  Demos  2001)  

 

In   its   most   extreme   form,   this   discourse   hence   calls   for   a   more   explicit   focus   on  conditional   equality   and   exclusion,   with   the   reintroduction   of   differentiated   legal   codes   and  zones,   and   ultimately   the   possibility   of   (preventive)   forceful   interventions   to   discipline   those  who   are   not   equally   sovereign   in   the   liberal   fashion.103   However,   as   has   been   shown   by  numerous  studies  on  global  governmentality,   the  norm  of   liberal   international  statehood  also  underlines   mundane   policies   on   aid   conditionality,   good   governance,   democratic   peace,  Washington   consensus,   as   advocated   by   the  major   global   governing   institutions,   to   produce  visible,   responsible   and   predictable   actors.   It   informs   the   numerous   indices   of   state  performances  and  governance  indicators,  on  the  basis  of  which  failed  states  are  identified  and  policies  for  their  transformation,  development  and  management  are  written,  using  mechanisms  of   more   indirect   rule   and   discipline,   such   as   the   production   and   review   of   country   reports,  providing  technical  assistance,  and  disseminating  best  practices.104    

Together,   these  discourses  and  practices  of  contemporary   international  society  shed  a  different   light   on   the   right   to   sovereign   equality   as   the   basis   of   international   order.  Contemporary   international   society,   its   universal   and   global   character   notwithstanding,   still  executes   its   ordering   functions   on   the   basis   of   the   alleged   schizophrenic   combination   of  tolerance   and   civilisation.105   In   this   context,   sovereign   equality   is   not   just   a   liberal   right   to  individuality,  but  by  the  same  token  operates  as  a  norm  to  be  equally  sovereign,  that  is  to  say,  to  be  a  sovereign  of  a  similar  (i.e.  liberal)  kind.  Sovereign  equality  hence  is  more  than  a  right  or  a  given  norm,  but  entails,   in  Cynthia  Weber’s  formulation,  a  process  of  normativity,   ‘whereby  “regular   subjects”   and   “standards   of   normality”   are   discursively   co-­‐constituted   to   give   the  effect   that   both   are   natural   rather   than   cultural   constructs’.106   It   is   in   this   light   that  we   can  understand  how  numerous  rules,  norms  and  standards  that  inform  contemporary  international  politics   function   as   modern   standards   of   civilisation   that   operate   on   the   very   basis   of   an  international  society  founded  on  the  principle  of  sovereign  equality.      

                                                                                                                         103  Lee  Feinstein  and  Anne-­‐Marie  Slaughter,  ‘A  Duty  to  Prevent’,  Foreign  Affairs    83  (2004):  136-­‐50;  Fernando  Tesón,  ‘The  Liberal  Case  for  Humanitarian  Intervention’,  in  Humanitarian  intervention:  Ethical,  Legal  and  Political  Dilemmas,  eds  J.L.  Holzgrefe  and  Robert  O.  Keohane  (Cambridge:  Cambridge  University  Press  2003),  93-­‐129  104  see  e.g.  Timothy  W.  Luke  and  Gearóid  Ó  Tuathail,  'On  Videocameralistics:  The  Geopolitics  of  Failed  States,  the  CNN  International  and  (UN)governmentality',  Review  of  International  Political  Economy  4,  no.  4  (1997):  709-­‐3;  Laura  Zanotti,  'Governmentalizing  the  Post-­‐Cold  War  International  Regime:  The  UN  Debate  on  Democratization  and  Good  Governance',  Alternatives  30,  (2005):  461-­‐48;  Jacqueline  Best,  'Why  the  Economy  is  Often  the  Exception  to  Politics  as  Usual',  Theory,  Culture  and  Society  24,  no.  4  (2007):  87-­‐10;  Oded  Löwenheim,  'Examining  the  State:  a  Foucauldian  Perspective  on  International  'Governance  Indicators'',  Third  World  Quarterly  29,  no.  2  (2008):  255-­‐27;  Iver  B.  Neumann  and  Ole  Jacob  Sending,  Governing  the  Global  Polity.  Practice,  Mentality,  Rationality:  Michigan  University  Press,  2010;  Hans-­‐Martin  Jaeger,  'UN  Reform,  Biopolitics,  and  Global  Governmentality',  International  Theory  2,  no.  1  (2010):  50-­‐86;  Tanja  E.  Aalberts  and  Wouter  G.  Werner,  'Mobilising  Uncertainty  and  the  Making  of  Responsible  Sovereigns',  Review  of  International  Studies  37,  no.  5  (2011):  2183  -­‐  2200;  Kevin  E.  Davis,  Angelina  Fisher,  Benedict  Kingsbury  and  Sally  Engle  Merry,  eds,  Governance  by  Indicators.  Global  Power  through  Quantificaation  and  Ranking  (Oxford:  Oxford  University  Press,  2012)  105  Keene,  Beyond  the  Anarchical  Society,  chapter  5.  From  a  Foucaultian  perspective,  discipline  and  freedom  go  hand  in  hand  in  governmentality.  106  Cynthia  Weber,  'Performative  States',  Millennium  27,  no.  1  (1998):  77-­‐95,  81  

 

Concluding  remarks  

This  article  discusses  equality  as  one  of  the  guiding  principles  of  international  society  from  the  perspective  of  the  politics  of  international  law.  However,  contrary  to  a  common  understanding  of  such  politics,  this  article  is  not  interested  in  the  true  motives  behind  colonial  or  hegemonic  legal  reasoning  –  was  international  law  instrumentalised  according  to  a  sceptical  reading  of  law  in  order  to  use  it  as  an  apology  for  colonial  or  hegemonic  politics;  or  did  these  scholars  see  law  as   an   objective   source   and   truly   believe   in   its   message   for   distinguishing   between   just   and  unjust  appropriation  and  the  identification  of  lawful  conquest?  This  article  is  more  interested  in  another  politics  of  international  law,  one  that  highlights  how  '[l]aw  is  politics,  not  because  law  is   subject   to   political   value   choice,   but   rather   because   law   is   a   form   that   power   sometimes  takes’.107  Addressing  international  law  as  a  governmental  technology,  this  article  explored  how  international  law  is  not  only  an  external  rule  of  constraint  imposed  upon  subjects  from  above,  but   is   a   productive   power   by   generating   the   subject   it   refers   to.   Or   to   put   it   differently,  international  law  as  a  regulatory  mechanism  produces  the  very  object  it  seeks  to  manage  and  control.108   And   in   the   case   of   the   colonial   encounters,   it   does   so   by   imagining   a   global   legal  order  that  the  aborigines  are  part  of  and  subjected  to.  Colonialism  hence  consisted  of  a  more  intricate   interplay   between   in-­‐   and   exclusion   as   basis   for   imagining   and  ordering   global   rule.  Yet,   as   Gong   has   also   suggested,   the   Standard   of   Civilization   ‘is   not   new,   nor  will   it    …    ever  become  old.  Some  standard  of  civilization  will  remain  a  feature  of  any  international  society’.109  After  decolonisation,  we  can  identify  the  imposition  of  an  implicit  standard  of  civilisation  as  the  paradoxical   outcome   of   the   universalisation   of   the   principle   of   sovereign   equality   and  expansion  of  European  international  society  to  a  globalised  one.  The  supposition  of  legally  ‘like  units’   in   effect   exposes   differences   between   formally   sovereign   states.   Having   sovereign  equality  as  a   right   then  recoils   in   the   form  of   the  validation  of  equality   in   terms  of   sovereign  being  on  the  basis  of  the  underlying  metavalue  of  legitimate  (or  ‘norm-­‐alised’)  statehood.    Acknowledgements  Earlier  versions  of  this  paper  were  presented  at  the  Annual  Convention  of  the  ISA,  San  Francisco,  3-­‐6  April  2013,  the  workshop  ‘Constructions of Globality’, Copenhagen, 17-18 June 2013 and  the  Annual  Millennium  Conference,  19-­‐20  October  2013.  I  would  like  to  thank  Moran  Mandelbaum,  Rens  van  Munster,  Erna  Rijsdijk,  Ole  Jacob  Sending,  Casper  Sylvest,  Jaap  de  Wilde,  Wouter  Werner,  Andrej  Zwitter,  the  anonymous  reviewers  and  editors  of  Millenium  for  their  helpful  comments.    

                                                                                                                         107  Pierre  Schlag,  'Foreword:  Postmodernism  and  Law',  University  of  Colorado  Law  Review  62,  (1991):  439-­‐,  448  108  Judith  Butler,  'Sexual  Inversions',  in  Feminist  interpretations  of  Michel  Foucault,  ed.  Susan  J.  Hekman  The  Pennsylvania  State  University  Press  1996),    59-­‐76,  64-­‐;  Foucault,  Security,  Territory,  Population.  Lectures  at  the  Collège  de  France,  1977-­‐78,  99  109  Gerrit  W.  Gong,  'Standards  of  Civilization  Today',  in  Globalization  and  Civilizations,  ed.  Mehdi  Mozaffari  (London:  Routledge  2002),    77-­‐96,  94  


Recommended