+ All Categories
Home > Documents > The Morality of Law and Economic Management

The Morality of Law and Economic Management

Date post: 26-Nov-2023
Category:
Upload: independent
View: 0 times
Download: 0 times
Share this document with a friend
15
1 The Morality of Law and Economic Management Abdulmalik M. Altamimi PhD Law Candidate, University of Leeds [email protected] Abstract This article explores the economic basis of Lon L. Fuller’s morality of law thesis and its relevance to discussions on the complex relationship between law and economics. Almost all the flaws in national and international economic institutions are the result of a failure to establish a proper balance between the aspiration for ‘an optimum allocation of resources’ and the duty to provide ‘legal rules conducive to security and predictability’. Both ‘aspiration’ and ‘duty’ constitute the two kinds of morality that Fuller recognises in his demonstration that ‘law is inherently moral’, and that he used to highlight the role of an institutional setting responsible for adjudicating rules for the allocation of economic resources. Keywords: Lon L. Fuller; Law and Morality; Interactional Legal Theory; Law and Economics; Legal Obligation; World Trade Law. Introduction ‘Legal craftsmanship must…be concerned with bending a received tradition to emergent social needs, exploiting the resources of law for practical ends. When the tension between these commitments is faced, jurisprudence comes alive.’ Philip Selznick 1 Since the publication of the revised edition of Lon L. Fuller’s book The Morality of Law in 1969 the application of Fuller’s jurisprudence had increased significantly, ranging from questions of ethics to constitutional law and international law. 2 Fuller has been admired by a number of scholars who applaud him for rejuvenating ‘the study of legal theory in the twentieth century’. He has also, however, been censured by some scholars for what one critic calls his ‘sloppiness’ and ‘flimsy arguments’. 3 It was the 1 Philip Selznick, ‘Review of the Morality of Law’ (1965) American Sociological Review 947 2 Lon L. Fuller, The Morality of Law (revised edn, Yale University Press 1969); David Luban, ‘Natural Law as Professional Ethics: A Reading of Fuller’ (2001) Social Philosophy & Policy 176; Roderick Macdonald, ‘Legislation and Governance’ in W. Witteveen and Wibren van der Burg (eds), Rediscovering Fuller: Essays on Implicit Law and Institutional Design (Amsterdam University Press 1999) 279-311; Jutta Brunnée and Stephen J. Toope, Legitimacy and Legality in International Law: An Interactional Account (Cambridge University Press 2010) (hereinafter An Interactional Account) 3 Robert Summers, Lon L. Fuller (Stanford University Press 1984) VII; Nicola Lacey, ‘Out of the ‘Witches’ Cauldron’?’ in Peter Cane (ed), The Hart Fuller Debate in the Twenty-First Century (Hart Publishing 2010) 1-42. For a critique of Fuller’s jurisprudence and its defenders see Matthew Kramer, ‘Scrupulousness Without Scruples: A Critique of Lon Fuller and His Defenders’ (1998) Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 235; cf Nigel Simmonds, ‘Straightforwardly False: The Collapse of Kramer’s Positivism’ (2004) Cambridge Law Journal 93
Transcript

1

The Morality of Law and Economic Management

Abdulmalik M. Altamimi

PhD Law Candidate, University of Leeds

[email protected]

Abstract

This article explores the economic basis of Lon L. Fuller’s morality of law

thesis and its relevance to discussions on the complex relationship between

law and economics. Almost all the flaws in national and international

economic institutions are the result of a failure to establish a proper

balance between the aspiration for ‘an optimum allocation of resources’

and the duty to provide ‘legal rules conducive to security and

predictability’. Both ‘aspiration’ and ‘duty’ constitute the two kinds of

morality that Fuller recognises in his demonstration that ‘law is inherently

moral’, and that he used to highlight the role of an institutional setting

responsible for adjudicating rules for the allocation of economic resources.

Keywords: Lon L. Fuller; Law and Morality; Interactional Legal Theory; Law and

Economics; Legal Obligation; World Trade Law.

Introduction

‘Legal craftsmanship must…be concerned with bending a received

tradition to emergent social needs, exploiting the resources of law for

practical ends. When the tension between these commitments is faced,

jurisprudence comes alive.’ Philip Selznick1

Since the publication of the revised edition of Lon L. Fuller’s book The Morality of

Law in 1969 the application of Fuller’s jurisprudence had increased significantly,

ranging from questions of ethics to constitutional law and international law.2 Fuller has

been admired by a number of scholars who applaud him for rejuvenating ‘the study of

legal theory in the twentieth century’. He has also, however, been censured by some

scholars for what one critic calls his ‘sloppiness’ and ‘flimsy arguments’.3 It was the

1 Philip Selznick, ‘Review of the Morality of Law’ (1965) American Sociological Review 947 2 Lon L. Fuller, The Morality of Law (revised edn, Yale University Press 1969); David Luban, ‘Natural

Law as Professional Ethics: A Reading of Fuller’ (2001) Social Philosophy & Policy 176; Roderick

Macdonald, ‘Legislation and Governance’ in W. Witteveen and Wibren van der Burg (eds),

Rediscovering Fuller: Essays on Implicit Law and Institutional Design (Amsterdam University Press

1999) 279-311; Jutta Brunnée and Stephen J. Toope, Legitimacy and Legality in International Law: An

Interactional Account (Cambridge University Press 2010) (hereinafter An Interactional Account) 3 Robert Summers, Lon L. Fuller (Stanford University Press 1984) VII; Nicola Lacey, ‘Out of the

‘Witches’ Cauldron’?’ in Peter Cane (ed), The Hart Fuller Debate in the Twenty-First Century (Hart

Publishing 2010) 1-42. For a critique of Fuller’s jurisprudence and its defenders see Matthew Kramer,

‘Scrupulousness Without Scruples: A Critique of Lon Fuller and His Defenders’ (1998) Oxford Journal

of Legal Studies 235; cf Nigel Simmonds, ‘Straightforwardly False: The Collapse of Kramer’s

Positivism’ (2004) Cambridge Law Journal 93

2

Oxford scholar in legal positivism, H.L.A. Hart’s challenge to Fuller in the

subsequently famous 1958 Harvard Law Review debate that made Fuller’s

jurisprudence popular.4 Without Hart, who played an equally pivotal role in the

rejuvenation mission, there would not have been Fuller’s subsequent elaborations on

his jurisprudence which made it more intelligible and applicable to the world of

jurisprudence today. Recent major works that built upon The Morality of Law thesis

includes Simmonds’ Law as a Moral Idea and Rundle’s book which refocuses attention

on ‘human agency’, i.e. on activism within the law as is implicit in Fuller’s concept of

‘legal morality’.5 A fundamental pillar in Fuller’s thesis that has not received much

attention in jurisprudence and its study in spite of its importance in national and

international legal obligation is the economic basis of The Morality of Law. The main

message of this article is twofold: first, to make the point that a minimum knowledge

of economics is essential to understand The Morality of Law thesis; and, second, to

highlight the fact that applying Fuller’s jurisprudence to issues that involve the use of

legal rules for economic management defeats the claim that moralising the concept of

law is fanciful. Throughout his thesis, Fuller uses the science of economics to explicate

the institutional design of law. This is not surprising given that Fuller’s first degree was

in economics, which also explains his strong support for socio-legal studies that include

economics and other social science fields.6

This article will show that The Morality of Law is acutely relevant to national and

international economics institutions because it defines the challenges of setting the right

balance between ‘aspiration’ and ‘duty’ in economic regulation and, more importantly,

explains how ‘fidelity to law’ is socially constructed.7 Fuller was aware of the

limitations of adjudicating rules applying to the allocation of economic resources in an

institutional setting. This makes his jurisprudence useful for discussing compliance

problems facing any institutional body that is responsible for adjudicating rules for the

management of economic resources. This article is structured as follows: Part One

provides a summary of Fuller’s legal theory; Part Two pieces together the references to

economics in Fuller’s The Morality of Law and other writings; Part Three offers five

reflections on the relevance of The Morality of Law to economic law and Part Four

concludes the article.

***

4 See H.L.A. Hart, ‘Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals’ (1958) Harvard Law Review

593; Lon Fuller, ‘Positivism and Fidelity to Law: A Reply to Professor Hart’ (1958) Harvard Law

Review 630; H. L. A. Hart, The Concept of Law (2nd edn, Clarendon Press 1997) 5 Nigel Simmonds, Law as a Moral Idea (Oxford University Press 2008); Kristen Rundle, Forms

Liberate: Reclaiming the Jurisprudence of Lon L. Fuller (Hart Publishing 2012) (hereinafter

Reclaiming Fuller). See Peter Teachout, ‘“Uncreated Conscience”: The Civilizing Force of Fuller’s

Jurisprudence’ in Witteveen and van der Burg (eds), Rediscovering Fuller (n 2) 229-254 6 Fuller was against the fragmentation of educational system with too much specialisation and lack of

interdisciplinary outreaches and engagements. For example, he wanted legal education to include social

sciences, chiefly economics. See Summers, Lon L. Fuller (n 3) 3,106,148 7 See Selznick, ‘Review of The Morality of Law’ (n 1)

3

I. A Summary of Fuller’s Jurisprudence

Before giving a summary of The Morality of Law it would be helpful to start by

providing an overview of Fuller’s interactional legal theory. Fuller’s notion of law is,

‘the enterprise of subjecting human conduct to the governance of rules’8. His concept

of morality is purely secular, as indicated by his choice of the word ‘enterprise’ to

highlight the fact that law-making is a human endeavour.9 The ‘human element’ has

always been prevalent in Fuller’s jurisprudence. He states, for instance, that the task of

legal philosophy is not only to provide a statement about ‘valid’ law but also ‘to give a

profitable and satisfying direction to the application of human energies in the law’.10

The notion of ‘an interactional law’ based on the principle of reciprocity is inherent in

a sentence that he wrote when opposing legal positivism and its inclination to ‘the

command theory of law’ where he states ‘if we could come to accept what may be

called broadly an interactional view of law, many things would become clear that are

now obscured by the prevailing conception of law as a one-way projection of

authority’.11 It was the contention of Fuller and natural law theorists before him that the

contemplation of the forms of law, i.e. the characters of legal declaration, would reveal

the moral content of law and its normative implications on human interaction.12

For instance, in a letter cited by Rundle, Fuller suggests that what his critics are missing

in their debates on the links between law and morality is a reference to ‘the conditions

antecedent to law’:

A legal system cannot lift itself into being legal by faith. Its security and

efficacy must rest on opinions formed outside of it, which create an attitude

of deference towards its human author (say, a royal law-giver), or a

constitutional procedure prescribing the rules for enacting valid law. To say

that this acceptance is ‘moral’ means merely that it is antecedent to law.13

Nonetheless, for a better understanding of Fuller’s jurisprudence it is useful to regard

law as being ‘an essentially ambiguous concept’.14 According to van der Burg, ‘an

essentially ambiguous concept is a concept which refers to a dynamic phenomenon that

can only be described and modelled in at least two different ways that are each

8 Fuller, The Morality of Law (n 2) 122 (emphasis added) 9 ibid 130 10 Lon L. Fuller, The Law in Quest of Itself (reprint edn, The Lawbook Exchange 2012) 2. See Lon L.

Fuller, Anatomy of Law (Penguin Books 1971) 59 11 Fuller, The Morality of Law (n 2) 221; Lon L. Fuller, ‘Human Interaction and the Law’ (1969)

American Journal of Jurisprudence 1 12 Fowler Harper, ‘Forms of Law and Moral Content’ (1929) Illinois Law Review 256; Rundle,

Reclaiming Fuller (n 5) 101; Colleen Murphy, ‘Lon Fuller and the Moral Value of the Rule of Law’

(2005) Law and Philosophy 239 13 Rundle, Reclaiming Fuller (n 5) 14 citing ‘untitled and undated document, paginated in hand as p

25’ (The Paper of Lon L. Fuller, Harvard Law School Library Box 12, Folder 4 ‘Encyclopaedia

Britannica’) 14 Wibren van der Burg, The Dynamics of Law and Morality: A Pluralist Account of Legal

Interactionism (Ashgate Publishing Limited 2014) 40

4

essentially incomplete and that are partly incompatible with each other’.15 Thus, an

ambiguous concept like the law can only be explained by ‘legal interactionism’ that

goes beyond viewing law as either a product (i.e. doctrine) or a practice (i.e. process)

to reach a ‘pluralistic’ account that treats law as a dynamic phenomenon made up of

different characteristics.16 For example, the law should be seen as a gradual concept,

comprising a plurality of sources that include interactional law, in the Fullerian sense,

and enacted law.17 For the purpose of this article, van der Burg’s definition of law as

‘an essentially ambiguous concept’ will only be used for the purpose of explaining law

as a product and as a process in accordance with Fuller’s jurisprudence.18 In fact, van

der Burg was right in saying that ‘the idea of essential ambiguity does not exclude the

possibility that law as a product and law as practice have at least some characteristics

in common that determine the distinctively legal’.19

In The Morality of Law, Fuller identifies three problems that led him to regard ‘law as

inherently moral’ and to perceive the close affinity between ‘the two moralities

[aspiration and duty], and the modes of judgment characteristic of economic science’.20

Fuller notes the first problem as being his ‘dissatisfaction with the existing literature

concerning the relation between law and morality’ because of ‘the failure to clarify the

meaning of morality itself’.21 Such failure is derived from the presumption that, when

the law is compared with morality, by virtue of this comparison it is readily assumed

that everyone knows what morality embraces.22 Fuller sees the manifestation of this

problem in the common misunderstanding of what the law actually implies and how it

can be distinguished from non-law.23 In addressing this problem, he proposes two kinds

of morality that reveal the moral content of law: the morality of aspiration and the

morality of duty. The former refers to the morality of the good life or ‘the expression

directed toward the achievement of human excellence’, while the latter refers to ‘the

conditions essential for orderly social living or existence’.24

The morality of aspiration resembles that of aesthetics - the artistic expression of

excellence - whereas the morality of duty resembles the law. The two moralities are

intertwined in that the morality of aspiration has ‘overtones of a notion approaching

that of duty’ through its consideration of the kinds of activity that are worthy of human

capacities and would fulfil the criteria of a good life.25 For instance, in recalling that in

contract law mutual misapprehension of relevant facts means that the agreement is void,

Fuller says, ‘what the morality of aspiration loses in direct relevance for the law, it gains

15 ibid 16 ibid 15 17 ibid 18 ibid 65-75 19 ibid 79 20 Fuller, The Morality of Law (n 2) 15 (emphasis added) 21 ibid 3 22 ibid 4 23 ibid 24 ibid 5 25 ibid 8

5

in the pervasiveness of its implications’.26 However, determining the relationship

between the law and morality, he notes a second problem concerning the failure to

address the morality that makes law possible, or what he calls the demands of ‘the inner

morality of law’,27 in the existing literature. To address this problem, Fuller focuses on

the problems of legal pathology resulting from the neglect of such demands.28 He

formulates the following eight moral tests of legality: ‘generality, promulgation, non-

retroactivity, clarity, non-contradictory, not asking the impossible, constancy, and

congruence between rules and official action’.29

Fuller associates these eight constitutive elements of legality with the morality of

aspiration, to show that they compromise ‘a moral ideal that is internal to the concept

of law’.30 Simmonds argues that Fuller’s systems, ‘count as law in virtue of their

approximation to the ideal of compliance with the eight desiderata’.31 According to

Rundle, this approximation affords respect for human agency ‘i.e. activism within the

law’.32 As she explains, in the Fullerian sense law is connected to morality:

In the moral dimension of law that consists in the ethos of the lawgiver’s

role and the distinctively moral burden which that role carries (…) in the

moral value that accrues to the legal subject, as a consequences of law’s

presupposed acceptance of and respect for her as a responsible agent.33

Before turning to the economics base of Fuller’s jurisprudence, it would be helpful to

briefly explain what he meant by ‘the external morality of law’. It should be reiterated

at this point that it is important for legal craftsmen to bend ‘the received [legal] tradition

to emergent social needs’.34 One way of doing this is by re-conceptualising the terms

‘justice’, ‘equality’, and ‘fairness’ before the law to meet the contemporary

manifestations of human needs. Fuller, who was concerned about such needs, used ‘the

external morality of law’ and ‘external aims of law’ interchangeably to refer to the

law’s substantive aims such as the principle of fairness. This means that the societal

concerns for justice ‘i.e. substantive ends pursued through law’ that he identified as the

‘the external morality of law’, should be guided by the principles of legality that he

associated with the inner morality of law.35 For example, writing about the neutrality

26 ibid 9 27 ibid 4 28 ibid 33-94 29 ibid 39 citing section 4 ‘Interaction in the Idea of Law’ in Kurt Wolff (trs, and ed), The Sociology of

Georg Simmel (The Free Press 1950) 186-189 30 Nigel Simmonds, Central Issues in Jurisprudence: Justice, Law and Rights (4th edn, Sweet &

Maxwell 2013) 256; Moffat argues that the law objective of ‘attaining legitimacy means that the

purpose of the principles of legality is…the achievement of optimum overall legality’, and the

complete failure to observe one of the principles, ‘can result in a failure to make law’. See Robert

Moffat, ‘Fuller, Lon L. (1902-1978)’ in Christopher Gray (ed), The Philosophy of Law: An

Encyclopaedia (Routledge 2013) 321 31 Simmonds, Central Issues in Jurisprudence (n 30) 258 32 See Rundle, Reclaiming Fuller (n 5) 33 ibid 101 34 Selznick, ‘Review of the Morality of Law’ (n 1) 35 Fuller, The Morality of Law (n 2) 4

6

of judges when interpreting statutes, Fuller said ‘the very same considerations that

require an attitude of neutrality with regard to the external aims of the law demand a

commitment by the judge to the law’s internal morality’.36 The interpretation of statute,

Fuller argued is ‘a process of adjusting the statute to the implicit demands and values

of the society to which it is to be applied’.37

To sum up, as a firm believer in ‘socialising’ the concept of law as an indispensable

basis for any jurisprudential inquiry of national or international law, the author of this

article endorses the claim that ‘legal morality’ empowers agents to act independently

and productively.38 Some of these agents, inspired by the history of people’s

interregional interactions in trade, established the institution of the market economy.

They accomplished this by relying on the principles of reciprocity and non-

discrimination and determining the validity of their actions based on institutional rules

having legal and moral bases. Hence, Fuller, who was also highly enthused by the

economic history of interactions and their achievement in advancing human prosperity,

understandably relied on economic science to explain the morality of law.

***

II. Economics in Fuller’s The Morality of Law and other Writings

The relation between law and economics, according to Fuller, is not merely determined

by the role of the law in mitigating or removing inequality, but by the translation of that

law into corrective and distributive justice that refocuses the attention on the role of the

institutional setting responsible for economic management.39 Aristotle’s distinction

between ‘corrective’ and ‘distributive’ justice, which was embraced by Fuller, means

that the latter is concerned with the restoration of ‘a previous relationship that has been

upset in some improper manner’, while the former refers to the nature of socially just

allocation of resources among the members of society.40 Viewing law within this realm

of social justice, Fuller argues, will facilitate the kinds of action that are taken to remedy

economic inequalities that ‘arise within a framework of legal compulsions’.41 Fuller’s

view on reciprocity is informed by his proposed, though never completed, project of

Eunomics, or the study of good social order.42 When he wrote about the concept of

‘freedom’, he made a distinction between ‘association by common aims’ and

‘association by reciprocity’.43 The former refers to parties joining forces to accomplish

36 ibid 132 37 Fuller, Anatomy of Law (n 10) 59 38 See Edwin Tucker, ‘The Morality of Law, by Lon L. Fuller’ (1965) Indiana Law Journal 270 39 Lon Fuller ‘Some Reflections on Legal and Economic Freedoms—A Review of Robert L. Hale’s

“Freedom through Law”’ (1954) Columbia Law Review 70 40 ibid 41 ibid 42 See Kenneth Winston (ed), The Principles of Social Order: Selected Essays of Lon L. Fuller (revised

edn, Hart Publishing 2001) 231-266 43 Lon Fuller ‘Freedom- A Suggested Analysis’ (1955) Harvard Law Review 1305.

7

mutually desirable goals that they could not attain individually, while the latter refers

to the principle of reciprocity in the literal sense of parties exchanging rights or

privileges for reciprocal gain.44 An organisation can be founded on the model of

reciprocity and still aspire to achieve common goals. A prime example of this, with all

of its flaws, is the World Trade Organisation (WTO). The WTO, to a large extent,

represents ‘the organization of market economy’ that Fuller elaborated on to advance

his thesis.45 Nevertheless, Fuller considers organisation by reciprocity to highlight the

challenge of providing a mechanism for an optimal realisation of the gains of

reciprocity.46 For him, ‘economic freedom’ cannot be discussed ‘in isolation from the

specific mechanisms or procedures by which that freedom is determined, or … by

which freedom to choose is allocated and conflicting choices are reciprocally

adjusted’.47

In relation to The Morality of Law and economic science, the third problem that Fuller

initially faced when he laid down the premises outlined above for his book and the one

he reiterated when he wrote about the substantive aims of law and institutional design

was ‘the proper location of the moral scale’s pointer’.48 He clarified this problem by

using the analogy of ‘a scale or yardstick that begins at the bottom with the most

obvious demands of social living, and extends upward to the highest reaches of human

aspirations’.49 He said that the difficulty with this moral scale was in locating the

pointer that ‘marks the dividing line where the pressure of duty leaves off, and the

challenge of excellence begins’.50 He explained this by saying:

If the pointer is set too low, the notion of duty itself may disintegrate under

the influence of modes of thought appropriate only to the higher levels of a

morality of aspiration. If it is set too high, the rigidities of duty may reach

up to smother the urge toward excellence and substitute for truly effective

action a routine of obligatory acts.51

Throughout his thesis and specifically to express this problem clearly, Fuller uses

economic management models to show the difficulty of locating such a pointer and the

interconnection and limitations of the two moralities. First, he selects two concepts

relating to economics: the first is concerned with ‘the relationships of exchange’ and

the second with what he regarded as something at the heart of economics, namely, ‘the

principle of marginal utility, by which we make the most effective allocation of the

44 ibid 45 Fuller even went further to say ‘this analysis [of the society of economic traders] suggests the

somewhat startling conclusion that it is only under capitalism that the notion of the moral and legal

duty can reach its full development’. Fuller, The Morality of Law (n 2) 24 46 Fuller, ‘Freedom –A Suggested Analysis’ (n 43) 47 Fuller ‘Some Reflections on Legal and Economic Freedoms’ (n 39) 48 Fuller, The Morality of Law (n 2) 170 (emphasis added) 49 ibid 9-10 50 ibid 170 51 ibid

8

resources at our command’.52 He regards marginal utility as being the economic

counterpart of ‘the morality of aspiration’ and the economics of exchange as having a

close affinity with the morality of duty.53 By way of illustration, Fuller explains that

when an economist is trying to create a stable and productive economy by advising

consumers on the most efficient ways of equalising the return for the money they spend,

the economist usually resorts to the ‘utility’ criterion, which is an undefined criterion

for the optimum allocation of resources.54 However, the ‘aspiration moralist’ who is

concerned with humans’ efforts to make the best use of their lives, is unable to define

what the best course of action for them is.55 Hence, it is within this undefined criterion,

relating to ideas about the highest economic or moral good, that the marginal utility

economist and aspiration moralist meet, ultimately leading both to the consideration of

the notion of balance.56 The primary concern of both the morality of aspiration and

marginal utility is maintaining the right balance in every life-fulfilling human

endeavour and this means that the prudent management of resources is of paramount

importance.57

The morality of duty, however, finds its closest kinship with the economics of exchange

and the duties that arise through the exchange of promises. Fuller maintains that ‘to

establish the affinity between duty and exchange’ there needs to be ‘a mediating

principle that can only be found in the relationship of reciprocity’.58 When trying to

answer the question ‘under what circumstances does a duty, legal or moral, become

most understandable and most acceptable to those affected by it?’, Fuller identifies

three conditions to achieve ‘the optimum efficacy of the notion of duty’.59 First, the

reciprocal exchanges of promises must be voluntary; second, the parties’ reciprocal

performances ‘must be equal in value’60 ; and, third, the relationship of duty must be in

theory and practice ‘reversible’.61 In answer to the question ‘in what kind of society are

these conditions most apt to be met?’ Fuller said:

[…] the answer is a surprising one: in a society of economic traders. By

definition the members of such a society enter direct voluntary relationships

of exchange. As for equality it is only with the aid of something like a free

market that it is possible to develop anything like an exact measure for the

value of disparate goods. Without such a measure the notion of equality

loses substance and descends to the level of a kind of a metaphor. Finally,

economic traders frequently change roles, now selling, now buying. The

52 ibid 16 53 ibid 54 ibid 17 55 ibid 56 ibid 18, 44-46 57 ibid 18 58 ibid 19 59 ibid 22 60 ibid 22 61 ibid

9

duties that arise out of their exchanges are therefore reversible, not only in

theory but in practice. 62

The challenge of setting the right balance between aspiration and duty, or what Fuller

called ‘supporting structure and adaptive fluidity’, is ‘shared by morals, law and

economics’, but is best epitomised by the economics of trade.63 However, when he

discusses ‘legal morality and the allocation of economic resources’ Fuller raises an

issue about the challenge of locating the pointer on the moral scale, this time to advance

this thought:

The task of economic allocation cannot be effectively performed within the

limits set by the internal morality of law. The attempt to accomplish such

tasks through adjudicative forms is certain to result in inefficiency,

hypocrisy, moral confusion, and frustration (…) As lawyers we have a

natural inclination to “judicialize’” every function of government.

Adjudication is a process with which we are familiar and that enables us to

show to advantage our special talents. Yet we must face the plain truth that

adjudication is an ineffective instrument for economic management and for

governmental participation in the allocation of economic resources.64

This cautionary note counterbalances Fuller’s earlier remarks that an authoritative

mechanism or procedure is needed so that ‘economic freedom to choose is allocated

and conflicting choices are reciprocally adjusted’.65 This call for an adjustment

mechanism supports the institutionalisation of economics, especially of trade, through

institutions of decision-making and dispute resolution. Since the economics of trade

was the focus of Fuller’s thesis, the following paragraphs shall provide a brief account

of one of the most developed institutions of trade, the institution of world trade.66

The reason for institutionalised trade is found in the model of comparative advantage

and the subsequent international economic theories that have improved this model. The

economist David Ricardo’s formula for dealing with the absolute advantage challenge,

the so-called ‘comparative advantage’, is the founding economic theory of international

trade.67 The theory stipulates that trade restrictions do not contribute to the state’s

economic welfare, and, ‘if nations specialise in those areas in which they have a

comparative cost advantage and trade where the advantage is lacking then there would

62 ibid 23 (emphasis added) 63 Fuller, The Morality of Law (n 2) 29 64 ibid 173, 176. See Lon L. Fuller, ‘Freedom as a Problem of Allocating Choice’ (1968) Proceedings

of the American Philosophical Society 101 65 Fuller ‘Some Reflections on Legal and Economic Freedoms’ (n 39) 66 For more on ‘the progressive legalization’ of world trade see Ernst-Ulrich Petersmann, ‘The

Establishment of a GATT Office of Legal Affairs and the Limits of ‘Public Reason’ in the

GATT/WTO Dispute Settlement System’ in Gabrielle Marceau (ed), A History of Law and Lawyers in

the GATT/WTO (Cambridge University Press 2015) 31(hereinafter, The GATT Legal Office) 67 Raj Bhala, Dictionary of International Trade Law (LexisNexis 2008) 85-88

10

be an overall increase in world production of the product in question’.68 For example,

if the United States (US) is superior at producing ‘wheat’, but less superior at producing

‘cloth’, which is China’s main product, then each can still benefit via the US investing

resources in what it does best – wheat production - and exporting its surplus to China,

and China doing the same with its ‘cloth’ and exporting its surplus to the US in

exchange for the wheat.69 Nonetheless, according to Bhagwati, ‘the Ricardian analysis

implied that this technical possibility of gaining from trade through specialisation

would only be realised if a policy of free trade were adopted in an institutional setting

where prices guided resources allocation’.70

Over the years, the Ricardian comparative advantage, designated ‘the law of

comparative advantage’, has provided the main rationale for legal rules oriented toward

freer trade. The theory has constituted ‘the stated logic for negotiating, drafting,

implementing, and enforcing rules to liberalise trade on a multilateral, regional, or

bilateral basis’.71 It was at the multilateral level under the rules of the 1947 General

Agreement on Tariffs and Trade (GATT), and later the 1994 WTO Agreements, that

legally binding rules for non-discriminatory trade relations between member states

were enacted. These world trade rules have to be fairly administered and adjudicated in

accordance with the trade rule of law criteria, and member states can only obtain a

derogation from these rules based on ‘general’ and ‘security’ exceptions under GATT

Articles XX and XXI. The GATT/WTO trade promises instantiate Fuller’s trade model

as being ‘voluntary in nature’, the reciprocal performances, with the exception of those

of developing countries, are ‘equal in value’, and the relationship of duty ‘is in theory

and practice reversible’.72 Moreover, the GATT/WTO rules largely instantiate Fuller’s

principles of legality, though they might be lacking in terms of the practice of legality.

Overall, the interaction between law and economics is evident in the relationship of

economic traders and the moral implications that this relationship raises. Thus, Fuller

was right in grounding The Morality of Law on the economics of trade as a useful

premise to illustrate his legal morality argument. It suffices to say that the immoral

wrongs committed in the course of conducting free trade or investments does not refute

The Morality of Law thesis. Going back to the first two arguments that Fuller uses to

68 Asif Qureshi, The World Trade Organization: Implementing International Trade Norms (Manchester

University Press 1998) 11 69 See Jagdish Bhagwati, Free Trade Today (Princeton University Press 2003) 4; Paul Samuelson, ‘The

Gain from International Trade Once Again’ Economic Journal (1962) 820; Gottfried Haberler, ‘Some

Problems in the Pure Theory of International Trade’ (1950) Economic Journal 223 70 Bhagwati, Free Trade Today (n 69) 4 (emphasis added) 71 Raj Bhala, International Trade Law: Interdisciplinary Theory and Practice (3rd end, LexisNexis

2008) 207 72 Fuller, The Morality of Law (n 2) 23; Fuller’s illuminating distinction between ‘norms of aspiration’

and ‘norms of obligation’ is important for highlighting the danger of mixing these norms in one trade

instrument leading states to regard ‘their strict obligations as mere aspirations’. See Wibren van der

Burg, ‘The Morality of Aspiration: A Neglected Dimension of Law and Morality’ in Witteveen and

van der Burg (eds), Rediscovering Fuller (n 2) 170 citing John H. Jackson, World Trade and the Law

of GATT (Bobbs Merrill 1969) 761-762

11

claim that ‘law is inherently moral’; namely, the failure to clarify the meaning of

morality and the morality that makes law possible, it can be inferred that any wrong

committed in the name of any subfields of economics was precisely because of the lack

of respect for the overarching concept of legal morality. Respect for this concept

invokes moral criteria that include not demanding the impossible of those subject to the

law and holding legal officials acting under the law accountable to the legal rules they

claim to defend. Therefore, a trade lawyer, for example, who claims that a trade policy

that deprives people of their only water resource is justifiable (contrary to the trade law

exception of prohibiting trade in exhaustible natural resources), is not acting based on

either moral or legal rule. Although Fuller was influenced by the phenomenon of trade

at the national level, his jurisprudence is also relevant to the theory and practice of

international trade, as the principle of reciprocity and the rule of law principle of non-

discrimination raise the same moral and legal implications for the practice of world

trade. In sum, both economists and lawyers need to understand the morality of law to

be able to appreciate the economic and legal aspects of their chosen fields and to be

able to support the rule of law principles of procedural fairness, equality, and justice.

***

III. Reflections on the Morality of Law and Economic Management

The summary given above invites the following five reflections on the link between

The Morality of Law and economic management. The first is that Fuller’s thesis is

useful when addressing the discussion that separately focuses on the fulfilment of

‘aspiration’ or ‘duty’ in economics without realising the close interactive relationship

between the two moralities and their internal connection to the concept of law. It was

not by accident that Fuller found economics to be a good basis for his Morality of Law

thesis as law and economics are intertwined. At the national level ‘law makes the

economy’,73 while at the international level ‘international law has always had

considerable ‘economic content’’.74 Fuller’s jurisprudence is relevant in this regard, as

it highlights the moral content of law in relation to the institutionalised economic

conducts of trade, finance and investment. By applying Fuller’s notion of law and his

inner morality concerning law criteria in reference to institutionalised conducts, The

Morality of Law will always have a positive bearing on such analyses. For instance,

those who are sceptical about the ‘judicialisation’ of world trade advocating

‘noncompliance’ for welfare objectives might be relieved to read about Fuller’s

scepticism about adjudication.75 However, from a historical perspective, the premises

of advocates who were labelled ‘anti-legalists’ and those of the ‘legalists’ who

73 Philip Allott, The Health of Nations: Society and Law beyond the State (Cambridge University Press

2002) 86 74 John Jackson, ‘International Economic Law: Complexity and Puzzles’, (2007) Journal of

International Economic Law 3 75 See Judith Goldstein and Lisa Martin, ‘Legalization, Trade Liberalization, and Domestic Politics: A

Cautionary Note’ in Judith Goldstein and others, Legalization and World Politics (MIT Press 2001)

219

12

remained entrenched in their belief that ‘judicialization’ is the only way forward, are

very distinct. This is true especially when one considers their take on the notion of duty

or obligation that arise from the reciprocal exchanges of promises and the proper

function of an institutional setting that organises such activity. Both the legalists and

anti-legalists seem to agree on the benefits of trade conducts guided by the principles

of reciprocity and non-discrimination, but they do not agree on the status of the

obligations arising out of these conducts or how they should be adjudicated. This is

why interactional law is relevant when it comes to highlighting the notion of obligation

in the institutional setting of economic traders who ought to use adjudication as the

appropriate mechanism of settling disputes. It is true that not every legal problem can

be aptly solved by a legal verdict, as there are other factors that influence the

functioning of society among them social or purely managerial factors that transcend

the subject of law.

However, the law always asserts its relevance in social interaction modes that are

working toward the achievement of a normative order. The question of whether this

order, once it has been established, can be best served by prudent managerial decisions

or legal rulings is a different matter altogether. For Fuller, legal texts matter but ‘the

source of normativity is social interaction’ guided by the principles of legality.76 What

is clear is that The Morality of Law is relevant when it comes to explaining the world

trade law with its competing aims of ‘an optimum allocation of resources’ and ‘legal

rules conducive to security and predictability’.77 The second point of reflection is that

this thesis is applicable to the conduct of finance as finance needs a concept of law with

a clearly identified ethical dimension. According to Fuller, professional ethical rules

have to be devised into aspirational ‘ethical considerations’ and mandatory

‘disciplinary rules’.78 A law concept drawn up with the idea that ‘law is separate from

morality’ will fall short of clarifying the ethics to be followed particularly in an

evolving field such as finance that urgently needs a clear ‘ethical code of conduct’. The

third point is that Fuller’s thesis is suitable for exploring the procedural justice of

economic institutions and addressing moral claims of wrongdoing.79 If the formation

of moral obligations was the direct result of sustained interactions on the basis of

reciprocity and non-discrimination, then surely those obligations have to be adjudicated

by procedural requirements infused with moral values.80 The Morality of Law will

become more pertinent once the social role of law, especially in terms of economic

conducts, is critically considered. For example, the clear analogy between harm-based

76 Robert Wolfe, ‘Kaleidoscopic Multilateralism: Lon Fuller, Rod Macdonald and the WTO’ in

Richard Janda and others (eds), The Unbounded Level of the Mind: Rod Macdonald’s Legal

Imagination (McGill-Queen’s University Press 2015) 90 77 Bhagwati, Free Trade Today (n 69) 4; John Jackson, The World Trading System: Law and Policy of

International Economic Relations (2nd edn, MIT Press 1997) 10 78 See David Luban, ‘Rediscovering Fuller’s Legal Ethics’ in Witteveen and van der Burg (eds),

Rediscovering Fuller (n 2) 193 79 Thomas Schultz, ‘The Concept of Law in Transnational Arbitral Legal Orders and Some of its

Consequences’ (2011) Journal of International Dispute Settlement 59 80 Simmonds, ‘Straightforwardly False: The Collapse of Kramer’s Positivism’ (n 3); Harper (n 11)

13

and duty-based moral restraints and the Fullerian moralities of aspiration and duty

propositions show the pertinence of Fuller’s thesis to research on ‘the moral foundation

of economic behaviour’.81 Moreover, trade experts’ deliberations on the ‘collective

moral responsibility’ to fulfil trade practices, highlights the suitability of Fuller’s thesis

as an appropriate analytical framework to address this contentious issue.82 Whether it

be research on the social, ethical or moral dimensions of economic law, The Morality

of Law can contribute to the research by revealing ‘the legal consciousness’ derived

from the actors’ interactions.

The fourth point is that the Fuller’s thesis is germane to addressing the distortions

arising from Posner Law and Economics Jurisprudence School with its ultimate goal of

‘wealth maximization’ at the expense of all human constructed values, moral or legal.83

The so-called ‘Chicago School of Jurisprudence’ that overemphasises the efficient

breach of contract, i.e. breach with impunity and the dilution of liability, i.e. the

discarding of responsibility, has done immeasurable harm to the study of law and

economics.84 In Fullerian terms, a theory that does not find its reason in either law or

morality and instead analyses legal obligations purely on the basis of economic

calculation will be devoid of any sense of justice. A society where breaching the law

‘efficiently’ means restoring some level of justice is prone to inequality and instability.

This school of jurisprudence is oblivious to the notion of moral obligation because it

neglects the aim of providing ‘security and predictability’ to economic actors to orient

their actions towards clearly stated rules of conduct.85 The terms stability, security, and

predictability are peculiarly alien to the law and economics school.86 The fifth point,

following from earlier remarks on the WTO, is about considering the applicability of

Fuller’s informed ‘interactional international law theory’ to the WTO given that some

scholars have claimed that this organisation suffers from the lack of ‘normative

consciousness’, public reason and an undetermined legal status.87 Petersmann, for one,

81 See David C. Rose, The Moral Foundation of Economic Behavior (Oxford University Press 2014) 82 Andrew Lang, World Trade Law After Neoliberalism: Reimagining the Global Economic Order

(Oxford University Press 2011) 353; Robert Howse, Joanna Langille and Katie Sykes, ‘Pluralism in

Practice: Moral Legislation and the Law of the WTO After Seal Products’ (2015). New York

University Public Law and Legal Theory Working Papers <http://lsr.nellco.org/nyu_plltwp/506>

accessed 2 April 2015 83 See Richard Posner, The Economics of Justice (Harvard University Press 1981); Alan Sykes and Eric

Posner, Economic Foundations of International Law (Harvard University Press, 2013); Eric Posner,

The Twilight of Human Rights Law (Oxford University Press 2014) in this book Posner criticized

human rights law, saying developmental aid should be preferred to the investment in human rights’

infrastructure. No explanation is given about how ‘aid’ can be protected from misuses. Such views of

human rights law, and preference for economic might over rights of individuals and states, are common

from anti-legalists. See Eric Posner, The Perils of Global Legalism (Chicago University Press 2009) xi 84 See Eric Posner and Alan Sykes, ‘Efficient Breach of International Law: Optimal Remedies,

“Legalized Noncompliance,” and Related Issues’ (2011) Michigan Law Review 243; John Dillbary,

‘Tortfest’ (2013) The University of Chicago Law Review 953 85 See Jackson, The World Trading System (n 77) 8-11 86 See Sykes and Posner, Economic Foundations of International Law (n 83); Posner and Sykes (n 84) 87 See Steve Charnovitz, The Path of World Trade Law in the 21st Century (World Scientific

Publishing 2014); Sungjoon Cho, The Social Foundations of World Trade: Norms, Community, and

Constitution (Cambridge University Press 2014); Petersmann, ‘The GATT Legal Office’ (n 66)

14

has rightly observed that the WTO law lacks ‘public reason’ and this can have a

detrimental effect on its enforcement.88 The interactional approach can contribute to a

better understanding of the causes of failure that emanate from either a lack of shared

understanding or rules that contradict Fuller’s principles of legality, or the lack of a

practice of legality in the WTO.89

With regard to the lack of public reason, the explications given above on the appropriate

role and form of law, as conceived by Fuller, are relevant in terms of the fulfilment of

the project of ‘cosmopolitan justice’.90 Fuller’s jurisprudence is helpful because it

contains the cosmopolitan aim of ‘respect for all those who are affected by the laws’.91

Thus, it is by applying the morality of law that the ‘deficiencies’ of the world trade law

can be identified and readily remedied. Furthermore, on reading Fuller, it is clear that

his ‘purposive interpretation’ conforms to the ‘internationalist model’ of interpretation

that gives effect to only those intentions of the lawmakers that serve the ideals of

justice.92 Continuing on this interpretation, it is fair to say that the content of a law, like

the world trade law, cannot be explained through reliance on Ronald Dworkin’s ‘legal

interpretivisim’. Unlike Fuller, Dworkin did not identify constraints on the lawgiver’s

power to respect the ‘inner morality of law’ and the essential role of human agency in

law-making and application. In brief, whether it is the national or international law of

economics, the Fullerian thesis is capable of providing the most comprehensive analysis

of legal rules made for one of the most important enterprises of mankind, i.e. the

prudent management of economic resources.

***

IV. Conclusion

Fuller’s preference for using economics to clarify the right content and purpose of law

is very clear. Re-reading The Morality of Law in light of the contemporary relevance

of its economic basis provides an instructive account of the complex relations between

law and economics. Various biographical accounts of Fuller’s life reveal his strong

enthusiasm for bridging the divide between economics and law. This is in addition to

his focus on the institutional role of law in adjudicating rules in economic disputes.

Communications between him and the constitutional political economy scholar, James

M. Buchanan, is a testament to Fuller’s enduring passion for a law and economics field

88 Petersmann, ‘The GATT Legal Office’ (n 66); See Ernst-Ulrich Petersmann, ‘Transformative

Transatlantic Free Trade Agreements without Rights and Remedies of Citizens?’ (2015) Journal of

International Economic Law 579 89 See Brunnée and Toope, An Interactional Account (n 2) 90 See Petersmann, ‘The GATT Legal Office’ (n 66); Frank Garcia, Global Justice and International

Economic Law (Cambridge University Press 2015) 205-272 91 S. Viner, ‘Fuller’s Concept of Law and Its Cosmopolitan Aims’ (2007) Law and Philosophy 1 92 Nicholas Mcbride and Sandy Steel, Great Debates in Jurisprudence (Palgrave 2014) 125. See the

Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties Articles (18) (31-33) that emphasis the ‘purposive

interpretation of treaties. For more on the moral purposive view of international law see Stephen

Allen, Law Express: International Law (2nd edn, Pearson Education Limited 2015) 6

15

of study, that does not rid law of its essential obligatory effect, or economics of its

marginal utility ideal.93 One wonders if Fuller were alive what would he have said

about Buchanan’s last book, The Reason of Rules (1985), which brought Buchanan’s

work even closer to Fuller’s elaborations on legal rules?94 The two scholars, who both

had to stand up to strong opposition by experts in their respective fields (Fuller for his

morality of law theory and Buchanan for his reasoning on economic rules), left us with

the enlightening legacy of an economic analysis of law.

Finally, The Morality of Law’s strong basis in economics does not negate the fact that

this thesis originally relates to the laws of lawmaking and the respect these laws afford

to human agency. Only by considering the inherently unjust laws in totalitarian regimes

and the newly made laws in ‘countries-in-transition’ that are striving to live up to the

principles of legality that Fuller identified can the moral content of law be fully

comprehended. The term ‘countries-in-transition’ refers to a group of countries that

are neither a stable democracy nor a stable autocracy but are going through the

upheavals of transitioning toward a nomocracy, i.e. to be ruled by laws not by a

government’s arbitrary will. 95 A useful connection in this regard can be made between

Fuller’s jurisprudence and the work of the political theorist, Hannah Arendt, who

perceived the law as being not an expression of command or the legitimate will of the

sovereign, but rather as a horizontal interactive mechanism for arranging the relations

between people within a society. How the lawgiver’s power could be constrained in

favour of the agency ‘i.e. activism’ of law subjects was the central question that equally

concerned Fuller and Arendt and scholars who studied their works.96 Overall, this

article main argument is that it is imperative, especially for economic law scholars and

lawyers, to contemplate The Morality of Law’s origins in economics that add to the

novelty and usefulness of Fuller’s jurisprudence.

93 Letters exchanged between Fuller and Buchanan, 8-13 January 1964, (The Papers of Lon Fuller,

Harvard Law School Library, box 2, folder 2) cited in Lacey, ‘Out of the Witches’ Cauldron’ (n 3) 30-

31; See James M. Buchanan, ‘The Domain of Constitutional Economics’ (1990) Constitutional

Political Economy 1 94 James M. Buchanan and Geoffrey Brennan, The Reason of Rules: Constitutional Political Economy

(reprint edn, Liberty Fund 2000) 95 See Beth Simmonds, Mobilizing for Human Rights: International Law in Domestic Politics

(Cambridge University Press 2009) 96 When the lawgiver overlooks his moral ethos to ‘rule by law’, and therefore resorts to violence, the

law-subject will find the moral imperative of revolt. See Kristen Rundle, ‘Legal Subjects and Juridical

Persons: Developing Public Legal Theory through Fuller and Arendt’, (2014) Netherlands Journal of

Legal Philosophy 212; Keith Breen, ‘Law beyond Command? An Evolution of Arendt’s Understanding

of Law’ in Marco Goldoni and Christopher McCorkindale (eds), Hannah Arendt and the Law (Hart

Publishing 2013) 15; Kenneth Winston, ‘The Inner Morality of Chinese Legalism’ (2005) Singapore

Journal of Legal Studies 313


Recommended