+ All Categories
Home > Education > Axiom of Choice Final Version

Axiom of Choice Final Version

Date post: 18-Dec-2014
Category:
Upload: gizemk
View: 1,628 times
Download: 0 times
Share this document with a friend
Description:
Axiom of Choice Final Version Math 101 Fall 2008
17
Axiom of Choice by Catherine Janes
Transcript
Page 1: Axiom of Choice Final Version

Axiom of Choice

by Catherine Janes

Page 2: Axiom of Choice Final Version

Set Theory Axiom 1 (the axiom of extension) Axiom 2 (the axiom of the null set)

Axiom 3 (the axiom of pairing) Axiom 4 (the axiom of union) Axiom 5 (the axiom of the power set) Axiom 6 (the axiom of separation) Axiom 7 (the axiom of replacement) Axiom 8 (the axiom of infinity)

Axiom 9 (the axiom of regularity)

Page 3: Axiom of Choice Final Version

The Axiom of Choice

Given any nonempty set Y whose members are pairwise disjoint sets, there exists a set X consisting of exactly one element taken from each set belonging to Y. (Lay 94)

Let {Xα} be a family of nonempty sets. Then there is a set X which contains, from each set Xα, exactly one element. (Garrity 207)

Page 4: Axiom of Choice Final Version

History

1924, S. Banach and A. Tarski

1939, Kurt Gödel

Early 1960s, Paul Cohen

Page 5: Axiom of Choice Final Version

When do we need it?

When we have a finite number of sets? let X1={a,b} and X2={c,d}. let X={a,c}.

When we have an infinite number of sets whose elements are well-ordered? well-ordering of the natural numbers

When we have an infinite number of sets whose elements are not well-ordered?

Page 6: Axiom of Choice Final Version

Shoes and socks

Shoes are well-ordered!

Socks are not well-ordered

Page 7: Axiom of Choice Final Version

Infinite Number of Sets

We can also say that all sets can be well-ordered.

“The Axiom of Choice gives no method for finding the set X; it just mandates the existence of X.” (Garrity 208)

Page 8: Axiom of Choice Final Version

Some Terms

A total order ≤ on a set E is said to be a well-order on E provided that, for each A a subset of E, there exists an m an element of A such that m ≥b for each b an element of A. The element m is said to be the maximal element of A (on E with respect to ≤).

Given S a subset of K, we say that q an element of K is a ≤-upper bound of S provided that s≤ q for each s in S.

A relation ~ on a set X is a partial ordering of X if it is transitive (if x~y and y~z implies x~z) and antisymmetric (x~y and y~x implies x=y) For example, ≤ is a partial ordering of the real numbers.

A partial ordering ~ on a set X is a linear ordering on X if for any two elements x, y in X, either x~y or y~x. Again, the relation ≤ is a linear ordering on the real numbers.

A linearly ordered subset E of X is maximal if any linearly ordered subset of X is contained in E.

Page 9: Axiom of Choice Final Version

Equivalentsto the Axiom of Choice

The well-ordering principle

Given any set A, there exists a well-order in A.

Recall:

A total order ≤ on a set E is said to be a well-order on E provided that, for each A a subset of E, there exists an m an element of A such that m ≥b for each b an element of A.

Zorn’s Lemma

Let X be a partially ordered set such that every linearly ordered subset has an upper bound. Then X has a maximal element.

Page 10: Axiom of Choice Final Version

Zorn’s Lemma

Hausdorff Maximal Principle –Every partially ordered set contains a maximal linearly ordered subset. Partial and linear order are meant with respect to the same ordering ~.

A relation ~ on a set X is a partial ordering of X if it is transitive (if x~y and y~z implies x~z) and antisymmetric (x~y and y~x implies x=y)

A partial ordering ~ on a set X is a linear ordering on X if for any two elements x, y in X, either x~y or y~x.

A linearly ordered subset E of X is maximal if any linearly ordered subset of X is contained in E.

Page 11: Axiom of Choice Final Version

Zorn’s Lemma

Zorn’s Lemma. Let X be a partially ordered set such that every linearly ordered subset has an upper bound. Then X has a maximal element.

Proof. Let M be the maximal linearly ordered set claimed by the maximal principle, which states that every partially ordered set contains a maximal linearly ordered subset. An upper bound for M is a maximal element of X. □

Definition: Let X be a set partially ordered by the relation ~ and let E be a subset of X. An upper bound of a subset E of X is an element x of X such that y~x for all y in E. If x is an element of E, then x is a maximal element of E.

Page 12: Axiom of Choice Final Version

Well-orderingCorollary of the Axiom of Choice. Let X be a set. There exists a

function f: 2X → X such that f (E) is an element of E for every E a subset of X. That is, one may choose an element out of every subset of X.

Proof:

Let f: 2X → X be a function, as in corollary above, whose existence is guaranteed by the Axiom of Choice. Set x1 = f (X) and xn= f (X – (union of xj for j=1 to j=1-n for n ≥2))

The sequence of {xn} can be given the ordering of the natural numbers and, as such, is well-ordered. A well-ordering for X is constructed by rendering transfinite such a process.

Page 13: Axiom of Choice Final Version

Let D be a subset of X and let ~ be a linear ordering defined on D. A subset E of D is a segment relative to ~ if for any x an element of E, all y elements of D such that y ~ x belong to E.

The segments of {xn} relative to the ordering induced by the natural numbers are the sets of the form {x1, x2, … , xm } for some m in the natural numbers. The union and intersection of two segments is a segment. The empty set is a segment relative to any linear ordering ~.

Denote by F the family of linear orderings ~ defined on subsets D of X and satisfying the following:

If E as subset of D is a segment, then the first element of (D – E) is f (X – E). (*)

Such a family is not empty since the ordering of the natural numbers on the domain D = {xn} is in F.

Page 14: Axiom of Choice Final Version

Lemma 1. Every element of F is a well-ordering on its domain.

Lemma 2. Let ~1 and ~2 be two elements in F with domains D1 and D2. Then one of the two domains, say, for example, D1, is a segment for the other, say, for example, D2, with respect to the corresponding ordering ~2. Moreover, ~1 and ~2 coincide on such a segment.

Page 15: Axiom of Choice Final Version

Let D0 be the union of the domains of the elements of F. Also let ~0 be that ordering on D0 that coincides with the ordering ~ in F on its domain D. By Lemma 2, this is a linear ordering on D0 and satisfies requirement (*) of the class F. Therefore, by Lemma 1, it is a well-ordering on D0. It remains to show that D0 =X. Consider the set

D′0 = D0 union {f (X - D0)}

and the ordering ~′0 that coincides with ~0 on D0 and by which (X - D0) follows any element of D0. Therefore, D′0 = D0. However, this is a contradiction unless (X - D0) is the empty set. □

Page 16: Axiom of Choice Final Version

Consequences of the Axiom of Choice

Set theory

Algebra

General topology

Page 17: Axiom of Choice Final Version

The Banach-Tarski Paradox

The Banach Tarski Paradox: Let S and T be solid three-dimensional spheres of possibly different radii. Then S and T are equivalent by decomposition.

S= T=

= and


Recommended