+ All Categories
Home > Documents > CS544: Lecture 3: Syntax and Compositional Semantics of the Noun Phrase

CS544: Lecture 3: Syntax and Compositional Semantics of the Noun Phrase

Date post: 12-Jan-2016
Category:
Upload: jesse
View: 47 times
Download: 1 times
Share this document with a friend
Description:
CS544: Lecture 3: Syntax and Compositional Semantics of the Noun Phrase. March 1, 2011. Jerry R. Hobbs USC/ISI Marina del Rey, CA. Noun Phrases. S. Last time we elaborated on VPs. NP. VP. V. NP. This time we’ll elaborate on NPs. The Relevant Parts of Speech. - PowerPoint PPT Presentation
Popular Tags:
35
CS544: Lecture 3: Syntax and Compositional Semantics of the Noun Phrase Jerry R. Hobbs USC/ISI Marina del Rey, CA March 1, 2011
Transcript
Page 1: CS544: Lecture 3: Syntax and Compositional Semantics of the Noun Phrase

CS544: Lecture 3:Syntax and Compositional

Semantics of the Noun Phrase

Jerry R. Hobbs

USC/ISI

Marina del Rey, CA

March 1, 2011

Page 2: CS544: Lecture 3: Syntax and Compositional Semantics of the Noun Phrase

Noun Phrases

S

NP VP

NPV

Last time we elaborated on VPs.

This time we’ll elaborate on NPs.

Page 3: CS544: Lecture 3: Syntax and Compositional Semantics of the Noun Phrase

The Relevant Parts of Speech

Noun (NN, NNS): singular and plural; “The _____ is ...”

Verb (VBN, VBG): broken, breaking; “_____-ing”

Adjective (JJ, JJR, JJS): good, better, best; “The ____ thing is ...”

Adverb (RB): very; often “____-ly”

Pronoun (PP): I, you, he, she, it, we, they, anyone, ...

Determiner and quantifies (DT): a, the, some, ....

Preposition (IN): of, in, to, during, before, ...

Page 4: CS544: Lecture 3: Syntax and Compositional Semantics of the Noun Phrase

The Structure of the NP

the three tall government buildings in Chicago that I saw

left modifiers right modifiers, noun complementshead noun

noun group

the three tall gray U.S. government buildings

determiners,numbers,quantifiers

adjectivesprenominalnouns head noun

In this order.

NP --> DT* JJ* NN* {NN | NNS} ....

You can use this structure to tell what part of speech a word is

Page 5: CS544: Lecture 3: Syntax and Compositional Semantics of the Noun Phrase

Nominal Compounds

What about:

State pension fundsGrammar induction techniquesWall Street reform effortCalifornia Public Employees Retirement System

One or more nouns can be placed before the head noun;This says only that some relation occurs between the adjacent nouns or noun sequences turpentine jar pension fund air strike city lights language origin grammar induction human languages

Bracketing ambiguities: [Stanford [Research Institute]] vs. [[cancer research] institute]

Noun-like adjectives can appear in this position too.

TreeBank does not tag these --“too hard to explain to annotators”

==> turpentine(x) & nn(x,y) & jar(y)

==> cancer(x) & research(y) & nn(x,y) & institute(z) & nn(y,z)

Page 6: CS544: Lecture 3: Syntax and Compositional Semantics of the Noun Phrase

The Adjective PositionA sequence of adjectives in their absolute, comparative, or superlative forms:

big investors the new chief executive a ferocious fire fightthe nation’s biggest public pension fund the Taliban’s ideological agendaa cursory look different sentences unannotated textual input

Adverbs can modify the adjectives or participles:

past internally driven geologic activity

Present and Past Participles can occur in the adjective position:

supporting air strikes resulting brawl numbed reflection stepped-up reform effort Present Participles can occur in prenominal noun position:

parking spaces its cratering record

Systematic ambiguity between adjective and prenominal noun: criminal lawyer resulting brawl vs. parking spaces

==> criminal(x) & lawyer(x) vs. criminal(x) & nn(x,y) & lawyer(y)

JJNN

Note incorporated particle

Page 7: CS544: Lecture 3: Syntax and Compositional Semantics of the Noun Phrase

Other Adjective Position Constructions

Measure phrases:

10-year fund veteran, 12.2% rise, six-foot high fence

Hyphenated passives with nouns: Los Angeles-based company cement-lined ramp

Hyphenated present participle (pre-participle noun is object): money-losing investments

Hyphenated or unhyphenated adjective-noun: medium-resolution images higher level units finite state languages

Note use of singular

Page 8: CS544: Lecture 3: Syntax and Compositional Semantics of the Noun Phrase

Determiners

The order of determiners (quantifiers, numbers) is a very random phenomenon that defies general principles:

not as few as ten too many other books

All the forest was destroyed any such book* All a forest was destroyed * such any book * a such book the three other books such a book three other books the other three books all three books* other the three books * both two books* other three books

Page 9: CS544: Lecture 3: Syntax and Compositional Semantics of the Noun Phrase

Some Determiner Phrases

Definite, Indefinite, Demonstrative: the, a, that, thosePossessive Pronouns: its, his, our, their, yourQuantifiers: each, all, such, An Ambiguity: some situations vs some computer program little (evidence)Determiner or Adjective? other, our ownNumbers and Related Words: two, 67 billion, several, many, most, four and a half (glasses)Complex Determiners: all our, all that, only a few, the two, just one or two, more than 100, a net 1,000, every last (one), the past 25 (millennia)

Possessive NPs also function as determiners:

the nation’s biggest public pension fund Afghanistan’s Uruzgan Valley Saturn’s satellites

Page 10: CS544: Lecture 3: Syntax and Compositional Semantics of the Noun Phrase

Count Nouns vs. Mass Nouns

Count nouns in the singular require a determiner: I showed him an example. * I showed him example.

Mass nouns don’t require a determiner in the singular: I gave him wine.

When mass nouns do have a determiner, it often means a kind rather than an instance. I gave him a good wine. (= a good kind of wine)

But there are many many idiomatic exceptions:

For example, by surprise, in front, in mind, He is president

Page 11: CS544: Lecture 3: Syntax and Compositional Semantics of the Noun Phrase

Structure of NPs: Left Modifiers all the many tall educated Washington presidential foreign policy advisors

Head noun: advisor’(e0,x) & Plural’(e1,x,s)

Prenominal nouns: Washington’(e2,w) & nn’(e3,w,x) Also noun-like Adjs: president’(e3,y) & nn’(e4,y,x)

Adjectives: tall’(e5,x) Also vbn, vbg: educate’(e6,z,x)

Quantifiers, Numbers: many’(e7,s) (property of the set in plurals)

Determiner: the’(e8,x, ....&e1) (relation between entity x and description given by rest of NP) Possessive NPs are determiner phrases: Amy’s => poss’(e10,a,x)

Predeterminer: all’(e9, s, ...&e1) (relation between set and description)

IN THIS ORDER

Page 12: CS544: Lecture 3: Syntax and Compositional Semantics of the Noun Phrase

Pronouns and Proper Nouns

It should be easy: No internal structure:

NP --> Pronoun (PP) I, you, he, she, anyone, one, ... NP --> ProperNoun (NNP, NNPS) Uruzgun Valley, Enceladus

But proper nouns sometimes function as nouns inside NPs, rather than full NPs: The Voyager 2 spacecraft The Cassini mission A resurgent Taliban

So maybe it’s better to treat proper nouns as simply nouns:

Noun --> ProperNoun

where in most uses it has no modifiers.

Page 13: CS544: Lecture 3: Syntax and Compositional Semantics of the Noun Phrase

Headless NPs

With some determiners, you don’t need a head noun:

I like those. * I like the. Give me some. * Give me a. You have many. * I want my. I don’t have any. the most the fifth-highest

They can also occur with right modifiers:

Those with siblings should stand up for them. Many in America don’t question authority.

Page 14: CS544: Lecture 3: Syntax and Compositional Semantics of the Noun Phrase

Recognizing Noun Groups with Finite-State Automata

Noun groups can be recognized fairly reliably with a finite-state automaton:

NG -->{ (Detp) (Adjs) Ns | Detp[complete] | Pro | N[time] | that N[sing] }

Detp[complete] -->{ ( { Adv[pre-num] | another | { det | Pro[poss] } ( only (other) ) } ) Number | Q | Q-er | (the) Q-est | another } | Det[complete,~that] | Pro[poss,complete] }

Detp[incomplete] -->{ { { Det | Pro[poss] } only | a | Det[incomplete] | Pro[poss,incomplete] } (other) | Detp[complete] other }

Adjs --> Adj ( ({ “,” | and | “,” and }) Adj )*

Adj --> JJ | VBN | VBG | Number “-” N[measure] (“-” JJ) | N “-” VBN }

Ns --> { ( JJ “-” ) N[sing,~time,~proper] }* N

Page 15: CS544: Lecture 3: Syntax and Compositional Semantics of the Noun Phrase

Logical Form of Noun Groups

Nouns convey three kinds of information: Singular nouns: “man”: the entity referred to: man(x) the property conveyed about that entity: man’(e,x) Plural nouns: “men”: the set s referred to the typical entity in that set: x A representation for “men”: man’(e,x) & plural(x,s) s is the set of men x is the typical man e is the property of x’s being a man

“tall presidents” ==> tall(x) & president’(e,x) & plural(x,s)“numerous presidents” ==> numerous(s) & president’(e,x) & plural(x,s)“former presidents” ==> former(e) & president’(e,x) & plural(x,s)

“the men ran” ==> run(x)“the men gathered” ==> gather(s)

Page 16: CS544: Lecture 3: Syntax and Compositional Semantics of the Noun Phrase

Logical Form of Noun Groups

Determiners and quantifiers are complicated in their logical form. Standard approach: all, every ==> (forall (x) ...) some, a ==> (exists (x) ...) the, these, such, .... ==> ?I would just say which of x, s, and e the word’s meaning depends on. many men ==> many(s) the man ==> the(x,e) [x can be identified by the description e] such men ==> such(x,e)

Possessives: Pat’s book ==> Pat(x) & Poss(x,y) & book(y)

Headless NPs: several arrived ==> several(s) & plural(x,s) & arrive(x)

Verbal forms in adjective position: running man ==> run(x) & man(x) broken window ==> break(y,x) & window(x)

Note object position

Page 17: CS544: Lecture 3: Syntax and Compositional Semantics of the Noun Phrase

Logical Form of Noun Groups

Verbal forms in adjective position: running man ==> run(x) & man(x) broken window ==> break(y,x) & window(x)

Possible positions for present participle: Adjective: supporting strike ==> support(x,y) & strike(x) Prenominal noun: parking space ==> park’(e,y,z) & nn(e,x) & space(x) Head noun: a brutal shooting ==> brutal(e) & shoot’(e,x,y)

Three types of adjectives (wrt logical form): Standard: red car ==> red(x) & car(x) Opaque: accidental guerilla ==> accidental(e) & guerilla’(e,x) (The person is not accidental, only the property of being a guerilla) Noun-like: Saturnian system ==> Saturn(x) & nn(x,y) & system(y)

Note object position

Page 18: CS544: Lecture 3: Syntax and Compositional Semantics of the Noun Phrase

Attributives

Some attributive adjectives have an implicit comparison set or scale:

A small elephant is bigger than a big mosquito.

That mosquito is big. mosquito(x) & big(x, s)

The implicit comparison set or scale,which must be determined

from context

Page 19: CS544: Lecture 3: Syntax and Compositional Semantics of the Noun Phrase

Proper Names

Proper names:

Could treat them as constants: Springfield is the capital of Illinois. ==> capital(Springfield, Illinois)

But there are many Springfields; we could treat it as a predicate true of any town named Springfield: capital(x,y) & Springfield(x) & Illinois(y)

Or we could treat the name as a string, related to the entity by the predicate name: capital(x,y) & name(“Springfield”, x) & name(“Illinois”, y)

Page 20: CS544: Lecture 3: Syntax and Compositional Semantics of the Noun Phrase

Indexicals

An indexical or deictic is a word or phrase that requires knowledge of the situation of utterance for its interpretation. “I”, “you”, “we”, “here”, “now”, some uses of “this”, “that”, ...

The property of being “I” is being the speaker of the current utterance

Indexicals require an argument for the utterance or the speech situation.

I(x,u): x is the speaker of utterance uyou(x,u): x is the intended hearer of utterance uwe(s,u): s is a set of people containing the speaker of utterance uhere(x,u): x is the place of utterance unow(t,u): t is the time of utterance uago(t,d,u): t is a duration of d before the time of the utterance u

Chris said, “I see you now.” ==> say(Chris,u) & content(e,u) & see’(e,x,y) & I(x,u) & you(y,u) & atTime(e,t) & now(t,u)

from the quotation marks

Page 21: CS544: Lecture 3: Syntax and Compositional Semantics of the Noun Phrase

Quantifier Ambiguities

Every man loves a woman. ==> ( m)( w) love(m,w) i.e., his wife ==> ( w)( m) love(m,w) i.e., Britney Spears

Most politicians in most countries can fool most of the people on most issues most of the time.

This has 120 possible readings, all distinct. e.g., different issues for each country, or same issues? different people for each issue, or same people?Do we need to generate each separate reading?

Quasi-logical form (Alshawi), typical elements (me) Specify the predicate-argument relations, remain silent about quantifier scoping

every(m,e1) & man’(e1,m) & love(m,w) & a(w,e2) & woman’(e2,w)

May later learn: FunctionallyDependent(w,m) i.e., ( m)( w)

Page 22: CS544: Lecture 3: Syntax and Compositional Semantics of the Noun Phrase

Right Modifiers or Noun Complements

Anything that can be a predicate complement can be a right modifier:

PP: the man in the black coat Adjective phrase: the people responsible, investors nationwide Past participle: the ingredients required for the recipe Present participle: those people seeking reelection NP (Appositive): Barack Obama, president of the U.S.

Think of these as “reduced relatives”: the man (who is) in the black coat

Also relative clauses:

the birds that I am able to identify ()

And a few other, less common constructions: Infinitival complements: an attempt to escape Sentential complements: the belief that America deserves better

Page 23: CS544: Lecture 3: Syntax and Compositional Semantics of the Noun Phrase

Prepositional Phrases

Some examples: a vital part of CalPERS’ efforts the Cassini mission to Saturn a ferocious fire fight with the Taliban a cautionary tale about fights breaking out the regularity of chunks over different sentences

PP attachment ambiguities are the biggest source of ambiguity in English:

I [saw [the whales in the bay] with binoculars. I [saw [the whales] [in [the bay with binoculars]]]. etc.

Usually attachments don’t cross:

Specify the length, in bytes, of the word.

Lots of ambiguities are benign:

I never spent enough time in one place. build a life for myself away from the job. bear little resemblance to the usual phrase structure.

Page 24: CS544: Lecture 3: Syntax and Compositional Semantics of the Noun Phrase

Adjective and Participle Phrases

Some examples: big investors nationwide the interest generated by Voyager’s visit

A classic ambiguity in computational linguistics:

I saw the Grand Canyon, flying to New York.

Page 25: CS544: Lecture 3: Syntax and Compositional Semantics of the Noun Phrase

Appositive NPs

Some examples:

Anne Stausboll, a 10-year fund veteran, the Australian counterinsurgency expert David Kilcullen a term, “accidental guerilla” chunking – recognizing higher level units of structure

Proper names can be the head, or the appositive.

Page 26: CS544: Lecture 3: Syntax and Compositional Semantics of the Noun Phrase

Logical Forms of Right Modifiers

PP: the cat in the hat ==> cat(x) & in(x,y) & hat(y) Sometimes arguments in relation nouns: mother of Pat ==> mother(x,y) & Pat(y)

Adjective phrase: the man responsible ==> man(x) & responsible(x,y)Past participle: the window broken by the boy ==> window(x) & break(y,x) & boy(y)Present participle: a student studying logic ==> student(x) & study(x,y) & logic(y)

Appositives: NP NP Barack Obama, president of the U.S. Use the predicate “be”: Obama(x) & be(x,y) & president(y,z) & US(z) or identity of variables: Obama(x) & president(x,z) & US(z) or predicate “Appos”: Obama(x) & Appos(x,y) & president(y,z) & US(z)

“Appos” usually means “be”, but can mean other things

Page 27: CS544: Lecture 3: Syntax and Compositional Semantics of the Noun Phrase

Some Other Right Modifiers

Time NPs: the summit last March ==> atTime(s,t)

Infinitival complements: the desire to fly ==> desire(x,e) & fly’(e,x)

“That” clause: the belief that the world is round ==> belief(x,e) & round’(e,y) & world(y)

Not an appositive becausesummit =/= last March

More like a PP

Like an appositive becausebelief = that the world is round

Not a relative clausebecause nothing’s missing

Page 28: CS544: Lecture 3: Syntax and Compositional Semantics of the Noun Phrase

Relative Clauses

One of the arguments or adjuncts is missing from the relative clause; the relative clause is a right adjunct on some head noun;that head noun “supplies” the missing argument or adjunct.

Simplest and most common case: the subject is missing:

fund which ( ) has lost more than a quarter of its value

the most momentous thing that ( ) had happened in their valley

storms that ( ) set the sky close to the ground

images that ( ) confounded planetary scientists

the gapthe filler

Page 29: CS544: Lecture 3: Syntax and Compositional Semantics of the Noun Phrase

Relative Clauses

Relative clauses in which the direct object or some other complement is missing:

the man I saw ( )

some form of chunked representation of sentences, which we might interpret ( ) as a phrase structure tree

Page 30: CS544: Lecture 3: Syntax and Compositional Semantics of the Noun Phrase

Relative Clauses

Relative clauses in which an adjunct is missing:

beliefs for which our forbears fought ( )

ways to turn these villagers into allies ( )

one way to capture the regularity of chunks ( )

Page 31: CS544: Lecture 3: Syntax and Compositional Semantics of the Noun Phrase

Why “Long-DistanceDependencies”?

the book that Chris thinks Pat said Kim read ()

NP

VP

V

SBAR

SIN

NP

NP

NP

NP

NP

VP

VP

S

SV

V

Page 32: CS544: Lecture 3: Syntax and Compositional Semantics of the Noun Phrase

Other Long-Distance Dependencies

Relative clauses are examples of long-distance dependencies, because the gap and its filler can be arbitrarily far apart in the parse tree.

the man that Mary believes John asked Susan to tell George to meet with ( )

To get the right logical form, we have to pass information about the gapup to the filler (or pass information about the filler down to the gap).

Other long-distance dependency constructions:Questions: Who does Mary believe John asked George to meet with ( )?Wh-nominalizations: Whoever Mary believes John asked George to meet with ( ) is here what was most revealing about the battle was the fact that ... asked later why they’d done so the question of how to learn structure from unannotated textual input

Page 33: CS544: Lecture 3: Syntax and Compositional Semantics of the Noun Phrase

Introducing Gaps in Clauses

The elegant way:

NP[gap=x] --> “ ”

The efficient way:

VP[gap=x] --> V[compl1=np] S[gap=x] --> VP

Passing gaps up to higher nodes:

S[gap=x] --> NP VP[gap=x] VP[gap=x] --> V NP (that) S[gap=x]

These work for gaps in questions and wh-nominalizations too.

x is some identifier of the nodethat is gapped

Gives us a gap in the object

Gives us a gap in the subject

Page 34: CS544: Lecture 3: Syntax and Compositional Semantics of the Noun Phrase

Filling the Gaps

The “wh-phrase” introducing the relative clause can be quite complex:

the man who I met ( )

the man the brother of whose father I met ( )

Rule: Replace the wh-word with the head noun. Fill the gap with the whole wh-phrase

Similar rules for questions and wh-nominalizations

Page 35: CS544: Lecture 3: Syntax and Compositional Semantics of the Noun Phrase

Logical Forms for Long-DistanceDependencies

the man who arrived ==> man(x) & arrive(x)the man whom Pat met ==> man(x) & Pat(y) & meet(y,x)the man for whom Pat works ==> man(x) & Pat(y) & work’(e,y) & for(e,x)the man whose cousin arrived ==> man(x) & cousin(y,x) & arrive(y)

whoever studies will pass ==> study(x) & pass’(e,x) & Future(e)


Recommended