+ All Categories
Home > Documents > Front Matter

Front Matter

Date post: 16-Jan-2017
Category:
Upload: duongtu
View: 217 times
Download: 0 times
Share this document with a friend
2
Front Matter Source: IRB: Ethics and Human Research, Vol. 33, No. 2 (March-April 2011) Published by: The Hastings Center Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/23048302 . Accessed: 12/06/2014 22:43 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. . The Hastings Center is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to IRB: Ethics and Human Research. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 185.2.32.141 on Thu, 12 Jun 2014 22:43:00 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Transcript

Front MatterSource: IRB: Ethics and Human Research, Vol. 33, No. 2 (March-April 2011)Published by: The Hastings CenterStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/23048302 .

Accessed: 12/06/2014 22:43

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

.JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range ofcontent in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new formsof scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

.

The Hastings Center is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to IRB: Ethics andHuman Research.

http://www.jstor.org

This content downloaded from 185.2.32.141 on Thu, 12 Jun 2014 22:43:00 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

IRB

ETHICS

March-April 2011 • Volume 33, Number 2

FEATURE ARTICLE

(Mis Understanding

Exploitation

HUMAN RESEARCH

FEATURE ARTICLE

(Mis)Understanding Exploitation Erik Malmqvist 1

Informed Consent Language and

Parents' Willingness to Enroll

Their Children in Research

Stephen John Cico, Eva Vogeley, and

William J. Doyle 6

Protecting Research Subjects: IRBs in a Changing Research

Landscape Ann Freeman Cook and Helena Hoas 14

by Erik Malmqvist

LETTERS 19

A Publication of

The Hastings Center

The

notion of exploitation frequently crops up in

discussions about the ethics of biomedical research. A standard concern about clinical trials is that

they exploit research subjects for the benefit of future patients. This concern is particularly emphasized

when participants in clinical trials are drawn from vulnerable social

groups and when research takes

place in developing countries.1

Some suggest that a major ratio

nale behind ethical principles and

guidelines governing research with humans is to avoid exploitation.2

Yet it is unclear what exploitation

means in the research context. The

lack of clarity is hardly surprising, since exploitation is not as well

established a part of the bioethics toolbox as other concepts, like

autonomy and harm. Exploitation

has also received comparatively

little philosophical attention out side of bioethics, and philosophers who have analyzed it disagree con

siderably about what exploitation

is, when it is wrong, and why.3 Although some authors in

research ethics have questioned

the usefulness of exploitation

discourse,4 recent works have

shed new light on the meaning of

exploitation in clinical research, and several common misconcep

tions have been identified and

dispelled.5 However, more concep

tual clarification is needed. This

Erik Malmqvist, "(Mis)Understanding Exploita tion," IRB: Ethics & Human Research 33, no. 2

(2011): 1-5.

paper is not an attempt to develop

a full account of exploitation in

research, nor will I try to system

atically apply any more general

theory to this particular case. I will

instead challenge one influential

way of talking about exploitation in the research context: the so

called nonexploitation framework that a group of leading research

ethicists have proposed in several

recent papers.6 I contend that one

core element of the framework—

the idea that nonexploitation in research requires that participants

are not exposed to excessive risk—

while seemingly sound, is in fact

quite mistaken and misleading. A reflection on exploitation in other

practices reveals why this is so.

The Nonexploitation Framework

The nonexploitation framework

is proposed as an alternative

to the long-prevailing view that clinical research should be guided by clinical equipoise.7 There are different interpretations of the clinical equipoise doctrine, but the central tenet is that conducting a

clinical trial is only justified when there is uncertainty about which

of the trial interventions is better.

On this view, randomization of research participants to different

trial arms is unethical when the

intervention in one of the arms is

clearly inferior to the intervention

in another arm (or to some other

intervention available in clinical

FEATURE ARTICLE

(Mis)Understanding

Exploitation

by Erik Malmqvist

The

notion of exploitation frequently crops up in

discussions about the ethics of biomedical research. A standard concern about clinical trials is that

they exploit research subjects for

the benefit of future patients. This concern is particularly emphasized

when participants in clinical trials are drawn from vulnerable social

groups and when research takes

place in developing countries.1

Some suggest that a major ratio

nale behind ethical principles and

guidelines governing research with humans is to avoid exploitation/ Yet it is unclear what exploitation

means in the research context. The

lack of clarity is hardly surprising, since exploitation is not as well

established a part of the bioethics toolbox as other concepts, like

autonomy and harm. Exploitation

has also received comparatively

little philosophical attention out side of bioethics, and philosophers who have analyzed it disagree con

siderably about what exploitation

is, when it is wrong, and why.3 Although some authors in

research ethics have questioned

the usefulness of exploitation

discourse,4 recent works have

shed new light on the meaning of

exploitation in clinical research, and several common misconcep

tions have been identified and

dispelled.5 However, more concep

tual clarification is needed. This

paper is not an attempt to develop

a full account of exploitation in

research, nor will I try to system

atically apply any more general

theory to this particular case. I will

instead challenge one influential

way of talking about exploitation in the research context: the so

called nonexploitation framework that a group of leading research

ethicists have proposed in several

recent papers.6 I contend that one

core element of the framework—

the idea that nonexploitation in research requires that participants

are not exposed to excessive risk—

while seemingly sound, is in fact

quite mistaken and misleading. A reflection on exploitation in other

practices reveals why this is so.

The Nonexploitation Framework

The nonexploitation framework

is proposed as an alternative

to the long-prevailing view that clinical research should be guided by clinical equipoise.7 There are different interpretations of the clinical equipoise doctrine, but the central tenet is that conducting a

clinical trial is only justified when there is uncertainty about which

of the trial interventions is better.

On this view, randomization of research participants to different

trial arms is unethical when the

intervention in one of the arms is

clearly inferior to the intervention

in another arm (or to some other

intervention available in clinical Erik Malmqvist, "(Mis)Understanding Exploita tion," IRB: Ethics & Human Research 33, no. 2

(2011): 1-5.

This content downloaded from 185.2.32.141 on Thu, 12 Jun 2014 22:43:00 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions


Recommended