+ All Categories
Home > Documents > Language, culture and the embodiment of spatial...

Language, culture and the embodiment of spatial...

Date post: 06-Feb-2018
Category:
Upload: vuongminh
View: 242 times
Download: 6 times
Share this document with a friend
25
Language, culture and the embodiment of spatial cognition CHRIS SINHA and KRISTINE JENSEN DE LO ´ PEZ* Abstract Our aim in this article is to argue that an adequate account of semantic development in early first language acquisition requires a theory and methodology that synthesize the insights of cognitive and cultural linguistics with a Vygotskian sociocultural approach to human development. This involves recasting and extending the notion of embodiment, which is a central philosophical underpinning of cognitive linguistics. We discuss evidence from the cross-linguistic and cross-cultural study of spatial semantic development, and argue that current controversies regarding language-specific acquisition strategies and universal cognitive bases of semantic development may best be resolved by viewing the issue of ‘‘linguistic relativity’’ in a sociocultural, as well as a grammatical, perspective. Keywords: linguistic relativity; space; semantics; acquisition; embodiment; Vygotsky. 1. Introduction: Embodiment and cognitive semantics [It] is always dicult for the psychologist to think of anything ‘‘existing’’ in a culture _ We are, alas, wedded to the idea that human reality exists within the limiting boundary of the human skin! Jerome Bruner (1966: 321) 1 The embodiment thesis is central to cognitive semantics, both as a general philosophical and psychological perspective, and as a source of specific hypotheses about linguistic meaning, metaphor, imagination, and cognitive mappings (Johnson 1987; Lako 1987; Lako and Johnson 1999). The embodiment thesis challenges the Cartesian dualism which Cognitive Linguistics 11–1/2 (2000), 17–41 0936–5907/00/0011–0017 # Walter de Gruyter
Transcript
Page 1: Language, culture and the embodiment of spatial cognitionprojekt.ht.lu.se/fileadmin/user_upload/project/ccs/5_Sinha... · Language, culture and the embodiment ... The embodiment thesis

Language, culture and the embodimentof spatial cognition

CHRIS SINHA and KRISTINE JENSEN DE LOÂ PEZ*

Abstract

Our aim in this article is to argue that an adequate account of semanticdevelopment in early ®rst language acquisition requires a theory andmethodology that synthesize the insights of cognitive and cultural linguisticswith a Vygotskian sociocultural approach to human development. Thisinvolves recasting and extending the notion of embodiment, which is a centralphilosophical underpinning of cognitive linguistics. We discuss evidence fromthe cross-linguistic and cross-cultural study of spatial semantic development,and argue that current controversies regarding language-speci®c acquisitionstrategies and universal cognitive bases of semantic development may best beresolved by viewing the issue of ``linguistic relativity'' in a sociocultural,as well as a grammatical, perspective.

Keywords: linguistic relativity; space; semantics; acquisition; embodiment;Vygotsky.

1. Introduction: Embodiment and cognitive semantics

[It] is always di�cult for the psychologist to think of

anything ``existing'' in a culture_We are, alas, weddedto the idea that human reality exists within the limitingboundary of the human skin!

Jerome Bruner (1966: 321)1

The embodiment thesis is central to cognitive semantics, both as a generalphilosophical and psychological perspective, and as a source of speci®chypotheses about linguistic meaning, metaphor, imagination, andcognitive mappings (Johnson 1987; Lako� 1987; Lako� and Johnson1999). The embodiment thesis challenges the Cartesian dualism which

Cognitive Linguistics 11±1/2 (2000), 17±41 0936±5907/00/0011±0017# Walter de Gruyter

Page 2: Language, culture and the embodiment of spatial cognitionprojekt.ht.lu.se/fileadmin/user_upload/project/ccs/5_Sinha... · Language, culture and the embodiment ... The embodiment thesis

has had such a long and pernicious in¯uence on traditional philosophyof mind, and which has been deeply in¯uential in modern linguistics and®rst-generation, ``classical'' cognitive science (Chomsky 1968). WhereCartesianism posits a formal and universal rationality, instantiated onlycontingently (but innately) in the human organism, the embodiment thesisstresses the continuity and motivating character of the relationshipbetween pre- or non-linguistic bodily experience, and cognition; and seeksdeep explanatory principles in human neurobiology. The embodimentthesis is consistent with current thinking in cognitive neuroscience(Damasio 2000). It is also consistent (when interpreted developmentally)with epigenetic connectionist computational modelling (Elman et al. 1996;Plunkett and Sinha 1992). The embodiment thesis is thus very much intune with the new, second-generation cognitive science which is steadilygaining ground, and indeed can be seen as one of the main philosophicalcontributions which cognitive linguists have made to this ``new'' cognitivescience.

Although the embodiment thesis, and in particular the linguistichypotheses which it has given rise to, is original and distinctive, itnevertheless has clear a�nities with earlier accounts in cognitivepsychology, as well as philosophy. Johnson (1987), for example, citesNeisser's (1976) ecological cognitive theory, and both Lako� and Johnsonexplicitly acknowledge the a�nity of the embodiment thesis with Gestaltpsychology. There is also an obvious similarity between the cognitivesemantic notions of image schema and force dynamics, and Piaget's (1953)account of the sensorimotor foundations of cognition in infancy. It isperhaps worth pointing out, in the light of Johnson's critical discussion ofKant's account of the imagination, that Piaget believed that the basicmotivation of his genetic epistemology was to provide a developmentaland biologically based reformulation of Kant's synthetic theory ofcognition (Piaget 1972a). At the level of speci®c formulation, it cannotbe denied that there are profound di�erences between Piagetian theory,with its emphasis on formal logico-mathematical models of reasoning, andthe theory of embodied cognition. Still, the fundamental motivatingimpulse of the two approaches is similar: to ground cognitive theory inthe biological properties of the developing human organism and itsinteractions with the physical world.

The Embodiment thesis also shares with Piagetian theory (and withdominant strands in cognitive psychology) an essentially universalistic andindividualistic vision of the mind. It would be wrong, and an over-simpli®cation, to say that Piaget entirely neglected the importance of socialinteraction in cognitive development. In fact, he stressed that socialinteraction was a necessary condition for cognitive development.

18 C. Sinha and K. Jensen de LoÂpez

Page 3: Language, culture and the embodiment of spatial cognitionprojekt.ht.lu.se/fileadmin/user_upload/project/ccs/5_Sinha... · Language, culture and the embodiment ... The embodiment thesis

However, entirely in keeping with his research program of elucidating theformal constructions that, he believed, constituted human intelligence,Piaget considered the features of the social environment necessary for thisconstructivist process to be in all essential respects trans-cultural:

Whether we study children in Geneva, Paris, New York or Moscow, in the

mountains of Iran or the heart of Africa, or on an island in the Paci®c, we observeeverywhere certain ways of conducting social exchanges between children, orbetween children and adults, which act through their functioning alone, regardlessof the context of information handed down through education. In all environ-

ments, individuals ask questions, work together, discuss, oppose things and so on;and this constant exchange between individuals takes place throughout the wholeof development according to a process of socialisation which involves the social life

of children among themselves as much as their relationships with older children oradults of all ages. (Piaget 1972b: 35)

Piaget did acknowledge that sociocultural factors could accelerate orretard stagewise development, to the extent that he suggested that, in somecultural settings, the ®nal stage of formal operational thinking might notbe attained by individuals. However, the order of development of stages isnecessarily invariant in his theory, being given by the logico-mathematicalformalization of the operations constitutive of each stage. In this sense, thesociocultural context of cognition2 and its development was seen by Piagetas simply a necessary and perhaps limiting condition, which could in hisview only modulate the pace and terminal point of a universal, endogenoussequence of cognitive development.

Piaget's theory of stages is no longer central to developmentalpsychology, but both the experimental paradigms which he pioneeredand the wider, biologically grounded, constructivist and epigenetic visionwhich informed his research continue to inspire some major currents incontemporary developmental psychology. However, since as far back asthe 1920s, and repeatedly until the present day, Piaget has also beencriticized by many developmentalists for his ``epistemic individualism''and his neglect of the sociocultural and communicative context ofcognitive development. Such criticisms have often been coupled withcriticism of his neglect of the speci®city of the cognitive domain oflanguage, and of its possible formative role in cognitive development.These criticisms were forcefully developed some 70 years ago by theRussian psychologist Vygotsky (e.g., Vygotsky 1978, 1986), whose work(to which we shall return) remains a basic reference point for the arti-culation of an alternative, more socioculturally oriented approach to thedevelopment of language and cognition (Bruner 1990; Sinha 1988). Thecase that we wish to argue here is essentially that the embodiment thesis,

The embodiment of spatial cognition 19

Page 4: Language, culture and the embodiment of spatial cognitionprojekt.ht.lu.se/fileadmin/user_upload/project/ccs/5_Sinha... · Language, culture and the embodiment ... The embodiment thesis

as currently formulated, su�ers from the same shortcoming as Piagetiandevelopmental theory: despite its many virtues, and its superiority to itsformalist rival, it has failed to pay su�cient attention to the importanceof culture and society in human cognition, in the motivation of linguisticstructure, and in the acquisition of language.

One rhetorical formulation of this critical point would be to say thatthe embodiment thesis breaks only with half of the dualistic frame-work of the Cartesian paradigm. Although it successfully challengesmind/body dualism, it leaves intact the dualism or opposition betweenthe individual and society, a residual dualism that leaves it open tothe dangers of collapsing into ``neural solipsism'' (Sinha 1999). LikePiagetian theory, the embodiment thesis pays a kind of lip-service tothe social surround, but does not explore its speci®c role in cognitionand language, and tends to see cognitive mappings in terms of a one-waystreet from individual (embodied domains) to society (abstract andsocial domains). Our aim is to explore this issue in relation to thecognitive and linguistic domain of space. We begin with a brief overviewof cognitive linguistic work on spatial semantics, a discussion of howthe embodiment thesis may be extrapolated to hypotheses aboutlanguage acquisition and language change, and a look at some evidencebearing on these hypotheses.

2. Spatial semantics, embodiment, universals, and cognition

The embodiment thesis can be stated as a general proposition:

[The] properties of certain categories are a consequence of the nature of humanbiological capacities and of the experience of functioning in a physical and social

environment. (Lako� 1987: 12)

Note that this formulation explicitly acknowledges both the interactivenature of the experience which gives rise to cognitive categories, and thefact that the environment in which the organism functions (and develops)is a social as well as a physical one. It does not, however, specify in whichways these two aspects of the organism's environment relate to each other;nor in what respects varying social environments may give rise to varyingexperiences; nor the extent to which such varying experiences may berelevant to the categories which are formed as a (partial) consequence ofsuch experience. The relevance of social experience is in no way denied, butit is not further explored, and, in most analyses, cognitive linguistsconcentrate exclusively upon the similarities and di�erences in thecategorial or conceptual structures which are expressed in speci®clanguages (and the typological relations between them). As we shall later

20 C. Sinha and K. Jensen de LoÂpez

Page 5: Language, culture and the embodiment of spatial cognitionprojekt.ht.lu.se/fileadmin/user_upload/project/ccs/5_Sinha... · Language, culture and the embodiment ... The embodiment thesis

argue, this self-limitation reinforces a limited and inadequate formulationof the (probably misnamed) ``linguistic relativity hypothesis''.

A further speci®cation of the embodiment thesis, which stresses theextent to which it can serve as a source of positive hypotheses, and to whichmost cognitive linguists (including ourselves) would subscribe, would readsomething like:

The human body (and nervous system) interacting with the physical (and social)world is the universal source of image schemas (and event schemas, force dynamicand motion schemas).

This formulation remains highly general, inasmuch as the nature of theinteraction (how frequent and how active does the subject's participation,for example, in an event-type, have to be in order for a schema to emerge?),and the extent to which such experience may vary between individuals andbetween cultures remains unspeci®ed.

Moving further in the direction of speci®c hypotheses, and evidencefor them, we can suggest that the embodiment thesis makes the furtherclaim that:

Embodied experience structures through metaphoric extension many othernon-physical (e.g. psychological and social-interpersonal) domains.

This is a central tenet of cognitive semantics and cognitive metaphortheory, and can be illustrated by awell-known example (Johnson 1987: 35):

[A] common type of metaphorical projection treats social or interpersonalagreements, contracts or obligations as bounded entities. This generates such

expressions as,4(a) Don't you dare back out of our agreement.4(b) If you want out, bow out now, before we go any further.

4(c) He'll weasel out of the contract, if he can.Being bound in this cases involves something metaphorically akin to being ina physical space where forces act upon and constrain you_So, to get out ofsuch a contract or agreement is to be no longer subject to its [moral or legal] force.

The ubiquity of such metaphoric mappings from the spatial (physical)to nonphysical domains does indeed attest to the psychological primacyor primitiveness of spatial schemas such as ``containment/constraint''.We know, too, from developmental psychological research that suchprelinguistic schemas (though not necessarily innate) are acquired early,well before the end of the ®rst year of life (Mandler 1996). A strong readingof the embodiment thesis would lead to the hypothesis that such earlyspatial schemas are directly grounded in bodily experience, in the sense ofmovements of one's body and of other objects in relation to one's body.

The embodiment of spatial cognition 21

Page 6: Language, culture and the embodiment of spatial cognitionprojekt.ht.lu.se/fileadmin/user_upload/project/ccs/5_Sinha... · Language, culture and the embodiment ... The embodiment thesis

Johnson (1987: 34) indeed proposes such a hypothesis, suggesting that``the projection of in±out orientation onto inanimate objects is alreadya ®rst move beyond the prototypical case of my bodily movement''(though he is careful to indicate that this is a speculative hypothesis, andto insist that his general proposition, that experience of physical space isprimary to the metaphoric spatial structuring of interpersonal relationsand social institutions, is una�ected by whether the speculation is corrector not). What can developmental psycholinguistic evidence tell us aboutthis hypothesis? We can note ®rst, that the speaker's body (or part of it)is frequently expressed (both as trajector, as in situations of beingpicked up and being put down; and as landmark, as in situations involv-ing putting on or removing clothing) in very early locative utterancesspontaneously produced by Danish, English, and Korean acquiringchildren (Choi and Bowerman 1991; Bowerman 1996; Thorseng 1997).Nevertheless, utterances in which the speaker's body, or part of it, is eitherlandmark or trajector do not seem to systematically precede utterances inwhich both landmark and trajector are other objects, either in generalor for particular expressions. There is no evidence, in other words, thatthe child's own body serves in these languages as a ``prototypical case''in learning to talk about spatial relations.

This ®nding provokes the question: What makes my body, as such,a more truly ``embodied'' or material realization of the schema of con-tainment/constraint than, for example, a cup, an artifact designed to bea container, and with which (in Western culture) infants learn to interactfrom a very early age? In fact, there is evidence that pre-linguistic infants(in England) already understand at the age of around nine months thatcups are containers, and that in order to function as such they must be intheir canonical, upright orientation (Freeman et al. 1981). We shall arguethat the question just raised is a fundamental one, which gives us a clue asto why the embodiment thesis needs to be extended ``beyond the body''. Inother words, we shall argue for an extended conception of embodimentthat is no longer restricted to the ``humanly corporeal''.

In summary of the developmental evidence discussed so far, we can notethat both spontaneous speech data, and experimental evidence regardingpre-linguistic cognitive schematizations of basic spatial relations, point tothe conclusion that early spatial schemas implicate ``non-self '' objectsand events at least as much as they implicate the developing child's ownbody. This does not preclude (though neither does it support) thepossibility that the child's own bodily actions in the physical world arecausal, as Piaget proposed, in the development of such early schemas.However, the data clearly argue against a strong developmental reading ofthe embodiment thesis, in which the human body would be hypothesized

22 C. Sinha and K. Jensen de LoÂpez

Page 7: Language, culture and the embodiment of spatial cognitionprojekt.ht.lu.se/fileadmin/user_upload/project/ccs/5_Sinha... · Language, culture and the embodiment ... The embodiment thesis

to be the schematic source for the later ontogenetic development ofspatial schemas.

Turning now to comparative linguistic evidence, one fact frequentlycited in favor of a strictly ``corporeal'' interpretation of the embodimentthesis is the widespread occurrence, in the languages of the world, ofconstructions in which body-part names occur in locative construc-tions (as in English ``at the foot of the hill'', ``into the mouth of the cave'',etc.). The use of body-part terms equivalent to ``front'' and ``back'' toexpress spatial orientation is widespread, and in some (predominantlymeso-American and West African) languages, spatial relational meaning(including, but not limited to, orientation) is linguistically conceptualizedregularly and obligatorily through the use of grammaticalized body-partterms.3 In some cases, such as the well-known one of Mixtec (Brugman1983; Lako� 1987), both animal and human body schemas are employedby speakers in the conceptualization of the landmark, while otherlanguages (e.g., those of the related Otomanguean Zapotec family) makeexclusive use of the human body schema (MacLaury 1989). It may beargued (although we are not aware of evidence on this issue) that incases such as Mixtec, the historically originary schema is that of thehuman body, and that the animal body schema is derivative. On the basisof an extensive survey, Heine (1997: 143) concluded that ``the ability touse the human body as a structural template to understand and describeother objects can be assumed to be universal; hence, we may expect thisto be re¯ected in all languages''.

However, the metaphoric domain±domain mapping between bodyparts and other domains is not unidirectional. Heine (1997) cites severalexamples of the recruitment of non-body part object names, and activity/experience terms including non-nominals, to designate body parts(e.g., French teÃte `head' from Late Latin testa `pot'; German Gesicht`face' from sehen `to see'). Furthermore, non-body-part locative expres-sions for psychologically basic or ``primitive'' spatial relational schemasmay themselves be recruited to designate body parts, while at the sametime the body schema is projected to spatial and nonspatial domains.Palmer (1996: 5) gives the following example from Coeur d'Alene,a polysynthetic North American language: the palm of the hand is the``surface in the back of the hand'',

a word analyzable into no less than ®ve morphemes:_NOM-IN-SURFACE-BACK-HAND. I would later learn that the spatial models that demarcate theentire surface of the body (but not the organs inside the body) and de®ne termsfor hands, ®ngers, toes, and many other body-parts also apply to Coeur d'Alene

place-names and even, metaphorically, to expressions for emotions and socialrelationships.

The embodiment of spatial cognition 23

Page 8: Language, culture and the embodiment of spatial cognitionprojekt.ht.lu.se/fileadmin/user_upload/project/ccs/5_Sinha... · Language, culture and the embodiment ... The embodiment thesis

What we should note here is that a body-part nominal is constructed out ofboth ``basic'' body-part terms, and non-body-part locative and object partterms, while at the same time the basic body part terms constitute thefoundation of a complex system of mapping of the human body schema tospatial and nonspatial domains.

From the linguistic evidence we have brie¯y overviewed, it seems thatbody part to object part and region mappings are highly frequent, andsystematic metaphoric construals of the entire domain of spatial relationsin terms of the human body schema are common. Nevertheless, ``reverse''mappings do occur, and body-part nominals are only one among thesources from which closed class locative items are derived (see later). Insum, therefore, we would conclude that the human body schema isa privileged, but not unique, source domain for the linguistic concep-tualization of spatial relations, and that its widespread recruitment forthis purpose re¯ects its universal experiential salience. To this extent, theembodiment thesis is empirically well founded. However, other sourcedomains (e.g., geophysical features, geographically or cosmologicallybased directional systems) also occur with high frequency, and this by thesame token also re¯ects their high experiential saliency. The embodimentthesis thus predicts a part of the relevant linguistic data, but is on itsown unable to account for all of it, unless extended to encompass at leastaspects and features of the experientially or ecologically signi®cant,noncorporeal world.

Taking a broader view, the domain of spatial relations manifests widecrosslinguistic variation in terms of the form classes employed and theirgrammaticalization sources (verbs of motion and disposition; locativenouns [including body-part nouns]; V- andN-derived adpositions; adverb-ials; particles; case in¯ections; verbal pre®xes and su�xes). The linguisticresources available to natural languages also vary widely in terms ofa range of cognitive and perceptual factors in¯uencing spatial schemati-zations, many of which involve the ``situatedness'' of the speaker'sbodily position in respect to a schematized referential situation, but notthe schematization of the body itself. These include frame of reference(Pederson et al. 1998); path speci®cation (Casad 1993); visibility±nonvisibility of trajector (Vandeloise 1991); speaker viewpoint (Casadand Langacker 1985). Finally, languages vary widely in terms of themapping patterns from schematization to expression, notably those ofcon¯ation (Talmy 1985) and distribution (Sinha and Kuteva 1995).``Embodiment'' is thus only one among many variables which cognitive(and other) linguists have found it necessary to take into account incharacterizing spatial semantics, and in beginning to construct a cognitivetypology of spatial conceptualization and expression.

24 C. Sinha and K. Jensen de LoÂpez

Page 9: Language, culture and the embodiment of spatial cognitionprojekt.ht.lu.se/fileadmin/user_upload/project/ccs/5_Sinha... · Language, culture and the embodiment ... The embodiment thesis

Amongst the almost bewildering array of linguistic conceptualizationsof space, body-part locative languages should provide privileged naturaltest-beds for psycholinguistic exploration of the embodiment thesis.What light might language-acquisition data from children acquiring sucha language shed? A hypothesis consistent with a strong reading of theembodiment thesis would be that children would consistently recapitulate,as it were, the grammaticalization history of the language, using thebody-part terms ®rst as nominals to refer to actual body parts (®rsttheir own, perhaps, and then those of others), and only later as locativeitems referring to spatial relations. An analysis was carried out by thesecond author (Jensen de Lo pez 1998, 1999) of her San Marcos TlapazolaZapotec acquisition corpus to test exactly this hypothesis. Zapoteclanguages are particularly suitable as a test for this hypothesis, since thebody-part nominal and its locative counterpart are morphologicallyidentical in many contexts, and the landmark noun phrase receives nogenitive marking when its relevant part or region is designated by thebody-part locative (BPL): it is hence not the case that the body-part locative construction is necessarily morphologically more complexthan a body-referenced nominal usage of the same body-part term.4

Jensen de Lo pez's analysis showed that the majority of those body-partterms which can be used in body-part locative constructions (a closedsubclass of seven body-part terms) ®rst appeared in the Zapotec corpus inthe body-part locative construction, not referring to an actual humanbody; and that early locative usage of body-part terms referring torelations between objects occurred more or less parallel with, and notsubsequent to, the use of the body-part terms to designate actual partsof human bodies. In other words (and consistently with the evidenceand arguments of Bowerman 1996), when Zapotec children learn to usebody-part terms, they learn to use them appropriately and consistentlywith the speech practices of the surrounding linguistic community, ratherthan assimilating them to an overriding basic meaning derived from theirexperience of their own bodies.5 To put it another way, they learn theirapplication in the presumed diachronic target domain simultaneouslywith their application in the source domain (for a similar argument inanother domain, see Johnson [1999]; and for a discussion of why we shouldnot, in general, expect ``ontogeny to recapitulate grammaticalization''see Slobin [1997]).

Our provisional conclusion is that neither linguistic nor psycholinguisticevidence provides unequivocal support for the embodiment thesis as it isusually formulated. That is to say, although the human body is (probablyuniversally) a salient potential source schema for the linguistic concep-tualization of space (and other domains), it is by no means the case that

The embodiment of spatial cognition 25

Page 10: Language, culture and the embodiment of spatial cognitionprojekt.ht.lu.se/fileadmin/user_upload/project/ccs/5_Sinha... · Language, culture and the embodiment ... The embodiment thesis

``bodily experience'' (if by that is meant experience of one's own body)provides the sole or most common schematic basis for construing space,or for acquiring the language of space. If embodiment is to remain (as webelieve it should) a central notion in cognitive semantics, it requiresa reformulation in terms which are psychologically (developmentally)realistic, and which link it more explicitly to systems of culturalschematization and understanding.

3. Linguistics, anthropology, schema, and world view

In this section, we situate the embodiment thesis in the wider engagementof cognitive linguists, and others, with the mutual relationships betweenlanguage, culture, and cognition. The triadic relationship of these threeterms is widely recognized to have constituted a fundamental ®eld ofscienti®c inquiry and debate since at least the time of Wilhelm vonHumboldt (1988 [1836]). Curiously, however, it is only relatively recentlythat all three terms have begun to be systematically treated together in themodern psychological, linguistic, and anthropological literatures. Morecommonly, the tendency has been to focus on the relationship between twoof the three terms (language and cognition; language and culture; cultureand cognition). In part, this may be because of traditional disciplinaryboundaries, and the tendency to compartmentalize human reality alongthe lines of these institutional divisions. It seems that interdisciplinarity iseasier to foster when it can be viewed as a ``border phenomenon'' betweentwo disciplines, giving rise to ``sub-interdisciplines'' such as psycho-linguistics/psychology of language, anthropological linguistics/linguisticanthropology, or (cross-) cultural psychology/cognitive anthropology.Simply listing these sub®elds is almost su�cient to illustrate theirinstitutional insulation from each other: textbooks and undergraduatecourses in (for example) psycholinguistics do not commonly refer tocultural-comparative data or theories.

Another reason for the common splitting of the triadic relation oflanguage, culture, and cognition into a triple of dyadic relationsÐwith``culture'', frequently, as the poor relationÐmay be that linguistics, inparticular, and psychology to a lesser but still signi®cant extent, have beendominated in the recent past by approaches based upon the notions ofmodularity, autonomy, and innateness. In such a perspective, languagevariation is interesting only for the light it sheds upon universal constraintsinherent in the language module(s); and grammar bears an arbitraryrelationship to the sociocultural surround, just as it is considered to beautonomous from linguistic meaning.

26 C. Sinha and K. Jensen de LoÂpez

Page 11: Language, culture and the embodiment of spatial cognitionprojekt.ht.lu.se/fileadmin/user_upload/project/ccs/5_Sinha... · Language, culture and the embodiment ... The embodiment thesis

The resurgence of interest in recent years in the ``linguistic relativityhypothesis'' (Lucy 1992a; Lee 1996; Gumperz and Levinson 1996) stemsfrom many of the same dissatisfactions with ``autonomous grammar'' ashave been partially responsible for the rise of cognitive linguistics, and hashelped to revitalize interest in language, culture, and thought. However,empirical studies of ``Whor®an e�ects'' have largely been couched in termsof the extent to which language in¯uences individual thinking (Levinson1996; Lucy 1992b; Pederson et al. 1998). In other words, the (at leastimplicit) reference to culture in views ranging from Humboldt, throughBoas, to Sapir and Whorf, which refer to language and ``world view'',has been downplayed in the narrowing of the problem-®eld to one ofindividual psycholinguistic functioning.

For Boas, ``the purely linguistic inquiry is part and parcel of a thoroughinvestigation of the psychology of the peoples of the world'' (Boas 1966[1911], cited in Palmer 1996: 11); and this inquiry was explicitly directedto the exploration of both di�erences and universals. It is likely that Boaswas in¯uenced in this conception by the ideas of Wilhelm Wundt. Wundt,though usually remembered as one of the ``founding fathers'' of laboratoryexperimental psychology, accorded equal importance (and devotedmost of his proli®c writing) to what he called ``VoÈ lkerpsychologie'', thepsychology of the peoples of the world, or (cross-) cultural psychology.In other words, the originating matrix for what later came to be calledthe ``linguistic relativity hypothesis'' was one in which anthropology,linguistics, and psychology were distinct, but related, moments of anintegrated inquiry into the mutual relations of culture, language, andthought.

Later in the twentieth century, the arbitrariness of the relationshipbetween linguistic structure and the sociocultural milieu of the languagecommunity became an article of faith for most linguists. SeveralreasonsÐincluding the notorious di�culty of de®ning the notion of``world view''Ðcan be adduced for this. First, in asserting the autonomyof its object, linguistics also asserted its autonomy, as a discipline, from thesocial sciences. Second, in di�erentiating comparative linguistics fromanthropology and sociology, linguists such as Bloom®eld pursued theprogramme, initiated by Boas, of distancing their scienti®c approach fromthe speculative (and not infrequently racist) evolutionism of nineteenth-century anthropology. It is not surprising, then, that Sapir and Whorfinsisted, despite the fact that their research materials were largely derivedfrom ®eld anthropological linguistic studies, that it was the grammaticalproperties of the language that in¯uenced the cognitive processes (habitualpatterns of thought) of the speaker, and not the cultural surround ingeneral.

The embodiment of spatial cognition 27

Page 12: Language, culture and the embodiment of spatial cognitionprojekt.ht.lu.se/fileadmin/user_upload/project/ccs/5_Sinha... · Language, culture and the embodiment ... The embodiment thesis

Linguistics and anthropology later achieved a partial rapprochementin the componential-analytic style of early, ``®rst-generation'' cognitiveanthropology (or ethnosemantics), which borrowed the ``etic±emic''distinction directly from linguistics, and which was predicated upon thehypothesis that cultural di�erence was to be captured in terms of thetaxonomic categorizations of speci®c cognitive domains (kinship; color;natural kinds), which are shared by individual members of a given culture,but not necessarily by members of other cultures. This approacheventuated in the important and well-known demonstrations by Berlin,Kay, and Rosch of the existence of universal cognitive foundations ofcategorizationÐthe story of which is told by Lako� (1987), and needsno repetition here. The approach as a whole, however, came to becriticized both for the static and atomistic conception of knowledge whichit shared with other varieties of structuralism, and for its reductiveconception of culture as the common denominator of individual cognitiverepresentations. To this criticism we can add that of Lucy (1992a): itsmethodology depended upon the identi®cation of conceptualization withlexical structure, and was unsuited to explore the relationship betweengrammatical construction and cognition that was the focus of Whorf'sthinking. In this way, ethnosemantics preserved the assumption that thegrammatical properties of languages (whether or not they a�ect ordetermine ``habitual thought'') are arbitrarily related to cultural-cognitivepattern or ``world view'', which ``penetrates'' language only to the depthof the lexicon and its structure.

Cognitive linguistics does not treat lexicon and grammar as modularlyseparate systems. Furthermore, it rejects the analysis of conceptualstructure in terms of ``classical'' taxonomies, employing instead thevocabulary of schema and schematization. It is worth noting in thisconnection that an early exponent of the ``schema'' notion was the social-cognitive and cross-cultural psychologist Bartlett (e.g., Bartlett 1932), whois best known for his pioneering work in the psychology of memory.Bartlett viewed the schema as both a universal principle of cognitiveorganization and a unit of analysis particularly suitable for revealingcultural di�erences in collective cognitive representations. This ``Janus-faced'' view of the schema as both a property of individual cognition anda characteristic ``model'' underlying cultural world view, has also beenemphasized by Shore (1996: 51), who points out that cultural schemasor models can be institutionalized:

cultural models have two quite di�erent lives: as social artifacts and as cognitiverepresentations_ Institutedmodels always lead a double life, as part of an externalsocial world and as products of intentional behaviour.

28 C. Sinha and K. Jensen de LoÂpez

Page 13: Language, culture and the embodiment of spatial cognitionprojekt.ht.lu.se/fileadmin/user_upload/project/ccs/5_Sinha... · Language, culture and the embodiment ... The embodiment thesis

Shore's examples of ``instituted models'' are ``conventional, patternedpublic forms'' such as discourse genres. In the following, however, we shalldraw attention to the way that material objects, too, can ``embody''intentional behavior and cultural-cognitive schemas.

If culturally speci®c knowledge or world view can fruitfully betheorized in terms of cultural-cognitive schemas; and if schematizationpatterns motivate linguistic structure (as is maintained by cognitivelinguists), then it follows that cultural schemas (and world views)should motivate, and be entrenched by (and not be ``determined by'', inWhor®an terms), linguistic structure. Indeed, precisely this reasoningcan be seen as underlying Lako�'s (1987) famous analysis of the Dyirbalnominal classi®er system. The most comprehensive recent treatment ofthe language±world view relationship, specifying it in explicitly cognitivelinguistic terms, is Palmer's (1996) path-breaking book on culturallinguistics (see also Palmer and Arin 1999). Palmer de®nes his researchprogram as follows:

Cultural linguistics is concerned with most of the same domains of language andculture that interest Boasians, ethnosemanticists and [ethnographers of speaking],but it assumes a perspective on those phenomena which is essentially cognitive.

(1996: 36).

By this he means that it employs cognitive linguistic concepts and analyses,in conjunction with ethnographic-linguistic methods. Palmer's innovationconsists not simply in the wealth of ethnolinguistic data that he reviewsand submits to cognitive analysis, but also in his proposal that

Linguistic meaning is subsumed within world view. Linguistic meaning isencyclopedic in the sense that it involves the spreading activation of conceptual

networks that are organized chains and hierarchies of cognitive models. Languageboth expresses and constitutes world view but could only fully determine it ina culture that lacked other means of expression and communication. (1996: 291;

our emphasis)

Again, we shall emphasize in the following that ``expression'' or``embodiment'' of cultural knowledge can also involve material culture.

The project of cultural (cognitive) linguistics represents, in our view,a major advance for cognitive linguistics, but it sits uneasily with theembodiment thesis. To put it simply, cognitive linguistics is now beset witha familiar contradiction within and between the cognitive and humansciences, which can be encapsulated in the following two propositions:

1. Linguistic meaning derives from embodied (individual) experience.2. Linguistic meaning is subsumed within world view.

The embodiment of spatial cognition 29

Page 14: Language, culture and the embodiment of spatial cognitionprojekt.ht.lu.se/fileadmin/user_upload/project/ccs/5_Sinha... · Language, culture and the embodiment ... The embodiment thesis

Can both of these propositions be true? Or do we require a dialecticalsynthesis that incorporates, while transforming, both of them (and, in thisconnection, especially the embodiment thesis)?

4. Cultural embodiment and semiotic mediation: An empirical study

At this point, we cast our attention back to a fundamental dispute indevelopmental psychology which emerged in the 1920s, but which con-tinues to provoke passionate disagreement and debate. The debateconcerned the role of culture, language, and social interaction in humandevelopment. The original protagonists were Piaget and Vygotsky. To givethe ¯avor of this debate, we provide three citations to add to that (fromPiaget) in the Introduction.

There is a logic of co-ordination of actions. This logic is more profound than thelogic attached to language and appears well before the logic of propositions.(Piaget 1963: 51)

Every function in the child's development appears twice: ®rst, on the social level,and later, on the individual level; ®rst, between people (interpsychological), andthen inside the child (intrapsychological)._All the higher functions originate as

actual relations between human individuals. (Vygotsky 1978 [1930]: 57)

Within a general process of development, two qualitatively di�erent lines, di�ering

in origin, can be distinguished: the elementary processes, which are biological inorigin, on the one hand, and the higher psychological functions, of socio-culturalorigin, on the other. The history of child behaviour is born from the interweaving of

these two lines. (Vygotsky 1978: 46).

Note, now, that if we substitute the term ``image schema'' for``co-ordination of actions'' in the ®rst sentence of the Piaget quote,we arrive at a reasoning that is in all essentials identical to the argumentby Johnson (1987: 38±40), that logical properties such as transitivity canbe derived from the properties of image schemas. Thus, if A is containedin B, and B is contained in C, it is a property of the physical containmentrelation, and not just of logic, that A is contained in C. And if thisproperty is preserved (as it must be) in the image schema for CONTAINMENT,then there is a logic of schematization which is developmentally prior topropositional or symbolic logic.

Now note, however, a further property of containment not notedby Johnson, but crucial to Piaget's famous experiments on ``object per-manence''. That is, that if a container is translated in physical spaceits contents are also translated in space. Move a cup of co�ee, and theco�ee goes with the cup. This property of containment is fundamentalto the basic human usage of containers, which not only topologically

30 C. Sinha and K. Jensen de LoÂpez

Page 15: Language, culture and the embodiment of spatial cognitionprojekt.ht.lu.se/fileadmin/user_upload/project/ccs/5_Sinha... · Language, culture and the embodiment ... The embodiment thesis

enclose, but also constrain the movement of their contents. We can callthis a functional, as opposed to logical, property of containment. In thereal, physical world, a container can only reliably subserve this functionif it is canonically oriented. Yet Piaget's experiments with infants involvedthe movement of an inverted container, and an invitation to the infantto ®nd the contents! To be sure, in the real physical world, if you move aninverted container with a trajector object under it, on a smooth supportingsurface, the trajector also moves, but this is arguably a di�erent andmore complex cognitive schematization than canonical containment.Freeman, Lloyd, and Sinha (1980) compared infants' performance ontwo simple variants of the ``object permanence'' or ``A-not-B'' task, onein which containers were canonically oriented, and one in which theywere inverted, and found that it was superior when the containers werecanonically oriented. In other experiments (reported in Sinha 1982, 1988),it was found that children in the age range of about 15 to 20 months, whenasked to imitate actions of placing an object in, on or under a cup con-sistently showed a bias towards placing the object in the cup, even when thecup was presented in an inverted orientation. Consistent with otherstudies, it was also found that children up to about 30 months of agedisplayed the same canonical ``in-bias'' when given language com-prehension tasks requiring them to put the object in, on or under anupright or inverted cup.

Di�erent explanations of these and other related ®ndings (Clark 1973;Wilcox and Palermo 1975) are possible, but taken in the context of a seriesof experiments (see also Freeman et al. 1981; Lloyd et al. 1981), it isplausible to conclude that the children's responses were dominated by thesocially standard, or canonical, function of the cup as a container, and thattheir understanding of this property overrode in many contexts bothlinguistic knowledge, and the physical spatial relations made possible, ora�orded by, the immediate perceptual array. Since functional properties,in this experimental design, are dissociated in some conditions from boththe a�ordances of the perceptual array, and the motoric complexity of theaction required to instantiate the visible or linguistically encoded target,the children's cognitive representations clearly involved functional objectknowledge. In other words, within a single developmental trajectory, youngchildren, we propose, are integrating (sometimes inappropriately!) sociallynormative knowledge of the canonical use of artifacts with their(biologically based) capacity for schematizing spatial relations; and itis at least consistent with the data that this cognitive representationalintegration is occurring from about nine months of age onwards.We deliberately formulate this extremely brief summary of complex dataso as to emphasize its a�nity with Vygotsky's point of view, but we

The embodiment of spatial cognition 31

Page 16: Language, culture and the embodiment of spatial cognitionprojekt.ht.lu.se/fileadmin/user_upload/project/ccs/5_Sinha... · Language, culture and the embodiment ... The embodiment thesis

emphasize at the same time that it presupposes a cognitive representa-tional capacity, which, just as Piaget proposed, is based in the ability to``abstract'' schematization from immediate perceptual content (see alsoMandler 1996).

The English language lexically di�erentiates the spatial relation ofcanonical containment (enclosure within a canonically oriented containersuch as a cup) from the spatial relation of enclosure within the boundedspace of an inverted container. The ®rst is lexicalized by in, the secondby under. In Zapotec languages, both schematic spatial relations arelexicalized by the body-part locative glossing to English stomach. Thiscross-linguistic di�erence is illustrated in Figure 1. The present authorstook advantage of the ``natural laboratory'' provided by this cross-linguistic di�erence to replicate the action imitation and languagecomprehension experiments already described, suitably calibrated to themost natural utterance forms in the respective languages, with Danish-(which for present purposes resembles English) and San Marco TlapazolaZapoteo-acquiring children. Our initial hypothesis was that, in line withthe ®ndings of Bowerman and her colleagues, the language-speci®csemantics of the Zapotec language under study would yield a di�erentresponse pattern for the Zapotec-acquiring children than that for theDanish-acquiring children in the language comprehension task. Speci®-cally, Zapotec spatial semantic structure, which schematizes an invertedcontainer as ``as good'' a ``container'' as an upright one, would inducea language-speci®c language acquisition pattern for Zapotec-acquiringchildren in which the ``in-bias'', or canonicality e�ect, demonstrated for

Figure 1. English and Zapotec lexicalizations of two schematic spatial relations

32 C. Sinha and K. Jensen de LoÂpez

Page 17: Language, culture and the embodiment of spatial cognitionprojekt.ht.lu.se/fileadmin/user_upload/project/ccs/5_Sinha... · Language, culture and the embodiment ... The embodiment thesis

English-acquiring children would either be abolished, or would be earlierovercome, in the language comprehension task, than for Danish-acquiringchildren, who would be predicted to show a similar (in-biased) responsepattern in language comprehension as English-acquiring children.Our experimental hypothesis, with respect to the language compre-hension task, was therefore derived from Bowerman's ``language-speci®cacquisition hypothesis'', which can be contrasted with a generalized``cognition hypothesis'' (Cromer 1974), which would predict universal(or universally motivated) acquisition patterns based upon prelinguisticcognitive development (including, perhaps, canonical-functional objectrepresentations) (see also Sinha et al. 1999).

Given that the action-imitation task is in all relevant respects ``non-linguistic'', that is, no locative items were employed in the instructionsto the children (which were of the form ``can you do what I did'', or``can you do the same''), and given that we were using containers thatwere culturally familiar for Zapotec as well as Danish children (wovenbaskets instead of cups), we expected that in this task we would ®ndsimilar response patterns on this task in the Danish and Zapotec samples.

The Zapotec experiments were prepared and piloted by both authorsand administered by the second author, during two of three ®eld visits tothe Zapotec community totaling 15 months. The Danish experiments weremainly piloted by the second author, and administered for the most partby trained assistants under the supervision of the authors. The data wediscuss were presented by the ®rst author during the plenary lecture of thesixth International Cognitive Linguistics Conference upon which thisarticle is based, and will also be part of the second author's Ph.D.dissertation. We have subsequently, in order to improve the numerical andage balance of the two samples, collected more Zapotec data, which isas yet unanalyzed. In order not to re-publish the same data at a futuredate, we are therefore simply giving a brief account of the ®ndings sofar, in the knowledge that the Zapotec database upon which the dis-cussion is based is incomplete, and must therefore be treated withcaution. Nonetheless, it should be emphasized that our summary is basedupon statistical treatment of the data, yielding statistically signi®cantdi�erences between the Danish and Zapotec samples.

As we had predicted, we found that the Danish children's responsepatterns resembled those of English children. The Danish children showeda canonicality e�ect (an ``in-bias'') on both the language comprehensionand the action imitation task, with the e�ect being overcome and thechildren reaching ceiling performance on the latter task at least six monthsbefore doing so on the former task. The Zapotec childrens' responsepatterns on the language comprehension task di�ered from those of the

The embodiment of spatial cognition 33

Page 18: Language, culture and the embodiment of spatial cognitionprojekt.ht.lu.se/fileadmin/user_upload/project/ccs/5_Sinha... · Language, culture and the embodiment ... The embodiment thesis

Danish children, in the expected direction, but perhaps more dramaticallythan we expected: not only was there a signi®cant di�erence between thesamples, but the ``in-bias'' was entirely abolished for the Zapotec sample,even for the youngest children. That is, there seemed to be no evidence ofa ``canonicality e�ect'' in the language comprehension task.

The data from the action imitiation task showed (against our pre-dictions) a similar pattern, that is to say, the Danish children's responsepatterns manifested an ``in-bias'' which was not present for the Zapotecchildren. In neither the language comprehension nor the action imita-tion experiment was the di�erence between the two samples attributableto a merely random responding of the Zapotec children; in fact (andperhaps partly because the mean age of the Zapotec children was some-what higher than that of the Danish childrenÐan important considerationin our subsequent collection of more Zapotec data) the proportion ofcorrect responses produced by the Zapotec children was slightly, but notsigni®cantly, higher than for the Danish children.

It is clear that these data cannot be accounted for by a ``universalist''cognition hypothesis. Bowerman's ``language speci®c acquisition'' hypo-thesis accounts for the language comprehension results, but does notaccount for the di�erence between the two groups of children in theirresponses in the action imitation experiment. The response patterns ofthe Danish children in both experiments were similar to those of Englishchildren on similar tasks in which the only di�erence was the speci®clandmark and trajector objects used (a basket and a grain of corn versusa cup and wooden building brick). It is plausible, then, to interpret theDanish children's response patterns in the same way as the Englishchildren's response patterns: the basket (like the cup) is conceptualizedas a functional container with a canonical upright orientation, and thereis a bias towards instantiating the function by placing the trajector inthe upright container.

How can we account for the absence, in either the language com-prehension or the action imitation experiment, of such a bias in theZapotec children's response patterns? One explanation would involveextending the language speci®c acquisition hypothesis to a strongWhor®an account, in which the semantics of the language beingacquired, rather than functional object knowledge, are responsible forerror patterns in both the linguistic (language comprehension) and thenonlinguistic (action imitation) tasks. We can hypothesize that theDanish and English prepositions i and in are both organized arounda core or ``impetus'' meaning (Vandeloise 1991) equivalent to canonicalcontainment. On the other hand, the San Marcos Tlapazola Zapotecbody-part term laÂani `stomach' is organized around a core meaning

34 C. Sinha and K. Jensen de LoÂpez

Page 19: Language, culture and the embodiment of spatial cognitionprojekt.ht.lu.se/fileadmin/user_upload/project/ccs/5_Sinha... · Language, culture and the embodiment ... The embodiment thesis

that equates to full enclosure, without pro®ling the orientation of thecontainer. Thus, the Zapotec language does not draw attention to theorientation of the container, and this aspect of linguistic meaning couldbe hypothesized to in¯uence nonlinguistic conceptualization as well aslinguistic conceptualization. The di�culty with this explanation is that itis very di�cult to see how it can be stretched to account for canonicalitye�ects in search strategies in the A-not-B tasks discussed earlier, ininfants as young as nine months. We cannot entirely rule out linguistice�ects on cognitive processes in such young infants, but the hypothesisis implausible.

A plausible explanation will, we suggest, need to take account not justof linguistic, but also of cultural di�erences between the Danish andZapotec groups (in such a way that it also accounts for the similaritiesbetween Danish and English response patterns). The explanation whichwe tentatively pro�er appeals to di�erences in cultural con®guration ofthe functional properties of containers in the di�erent cultural settings.Could it be that the Zapotec children did not display an ``in-bias'' in theirresponse patterns for the reason that baskets are not used as canonicalcontainers in the same way that cups are in Danish culture? In support ofsuch a hypothesis, we can make the following observations. The Zapotecculture makes use of a smaller variety of artifacts than the Danish culture,and tends to employ them ¯exibly and multi-functionally. In the villagewhere the Zapotec study was conducted, baskets are commonly used, in``inverted'' orientation, as ``covers'' for tortillas and other food items, andare stacked for storage in inverted orientation. They are also frequentlyused in inverted orientation in children's games, for example in catchingchickens. Inverted baskets are sometimes placed over brooding chickensin order to keep them on their eggs, so that the eggs will hatch. Ifthe ``core'' or impetus containment schema involves constraint by thelandmark of the location of the trajector, it would seem that in this culture,at least, the schema is not canonically associated with an orientation ofthe container with its cavity upwards.

Although baskets are not the only containers in use in the Zapotecvillage (for example, there are also gourds, bottles, and the occasionalglass for special occasions), cups are quite uncommon. In contrast, inDanish culture, developing infants are not only exposed at an early ageto cups, but their actions with and upon cups are shaped by adultstowards drinking from (and not spilling liquids from) and playingwith upright cups.

Our suggestion, then, is that a nonlinguistic sociocultural di�erenceregarding canonical artifact use, embodied in the material cultures andexempli®ed in nonlinguistic cultural practices, gives rise to slightly but

The embodiment of spatial cognition 35

Page 20: Language, culture and the embodiment of spatial cognitionprojekt.ht.lu.se/fileadmin/user_upload/project/ccs/5_Sinha... · Language, culture and the embodiment ... The embodiment thesis

signi®cantly di�erent conceptualizations of ``containment'' in the di�erentcultures. This di�erence is (perhaps motivatedly) reproduced or paralleledin the spatial semantics of the Danish and Zapotec languages. Language-acquiring children are ``predisposed'', through their experiences of inter-action with the material world as this is culturally presented, and throughthe mediation of cultural practices, to employ comprehension strategiesthat are consistent with the speci®c semantics of the languages theyare acquiring. Acquisition of, and experience of using, language sub-sequently entrenches this socioculturally based cognitive di�erence(rather than, as in the conventional reading of the Whor®an hypothesis,causing or determining it).

This interpretation constitutes a hypothesis that can be subjected to test,by attempting to vary language and culture as separate variables; but italso suggests that these will never be true ``independent variables''. We arecurrently extending the languages and cultures under study in order to testthe hypothesis, and it cannot be treated as any more than that at present.If, however, our interpretation proves robust in the face of new evidence,it would provide clear evidence of the operation in human developmentof what Vygotsky called the ``semiotic mediation'' of higher cognition;a process which he considered, indeed, to be constitutive of higher cognitivefunctions; and which includes but is not restricted to the mediation ofthought by language. The hypothesis that we are arguing for is that theeveryday artifacts used in the experiments are not ``culturally neutral'', notjust in the sense that they may be more or less familiar to individuals fromdi�erent cultures, but also because they embody di�erent conceptualiza-tions or cultural schemas (in this case, of spatial relations). This ``extendedembodiment'' does not exist in a vacuum: it is not, as it were, a propertyof the objects ``in themselves''. Rather, it is constituted and exempli®ed bythe participation of the objects in an entire matrix of cultural practices,some of which are linguistic (or discursive) practices, and some of whichare nonlinguistic. Furthermore, cultural schemas ®nd a further mani-festation, or expression, in the lexico-grammatical structures of naturallanguages, and it is from this perspective perhaps no surprise that childrenshould be so adept, as Bowerman and her colleagues have shown, inacquiring the speci®c conceptualization±expression mappings of theirmother tongue.

5. Conclusion

In this article we have argued that the embodiment thesis needs to beextended to take account of the role of cultural meaning in motivating

36 C. Sinha and K. Jensen de LoÂpez

Page 21: Language, culture and the embodiment of spatial cognitionprojekt.ht.lu.se/fileadmin/user_upload/project/ccs/5_Sinha... · Language, culture and the embodiment ... The embodiment thesis

linguistic structure and, more widely, the sociocultural groundingof language. We argue as well that the so-called ``linguistic relativityhypothesis'' also requires reformulation and extension, to take accountof nonlinguistic expressions and embodiments of culture. The vehiclewe choose for ``extending embodiment beyond the human body'' isVygotsky's sociocultural, or cultural-historical, developmental psycho-logy. We o�er an empirical example of a cross-cultural and cross-linguisticdi�erence in the development of language and cognition, and o�er anexplanation of these di�erences in terms of language ``entrenching''cognitive di�erences induced by cultural embodiment and culturalpractice. In conclusion, we believe that a serious theoretical and empiricaldialogue between cognitive linguistics and sociocultural approaches tolanguage and mind can only be of bene®t to both; this article is intendedas a contribution to such a dialogue.

Received 5 July 2000 University of Southern Denmark

Revision received 15 September 2000 Odense, Denmark

Notes

* The authors can be contacted at the University of Southern Denmark, Department

of Language and Communication, Campusvej 55, 5230 Odense M, Denmark.

E-mail: [email protected]

1. We are grateful to Andrew Lock for this apt quotation (Lock 2000).

2. We do not intend to distinguish here between ``culture'', ``society'' and ``sociocultural

context''. Although they are not the same, for our purposes the ``sociocultural'' embraces

social structures and practices whichmay or may not be typical only for a particular given

culture or group of cultures, as well as symbolic andmaterial cultures and their associated

practices.

3. Body-part terms are also recruited for lexical and grammatical usage in other cognitive

domains, notably numeral systems.

4. The body-part locative and the body-part noun from which it is derived can be

distinguished on grammatical grounds, and precisely this distinguishability is evidence for

the grammaticalization of the body-part locative. The landmark of which the spatial

relation expressed by the body-part locative is predicated can be expressed either by a NP

or by a ``personal pronominal'' clitic su�x identical to person marking on verbs (Munro

and Lo pez 1999). The general point about morphological indistinguishability in many

contexts stands however. Where the landmark is expressed by a NP, the body-part

expression may be ambiguous as between usage as object part and usage as locative,

e.g., quia yuu `head house'may refer either to the roof (part) of the house or to the location

on or above the roof of the house (there is no alternative lexicalization of ``roof '' to

the use of the body-part term).

5. It is worth noting that the body-part term lo, `face', also occurs in dative constructions,

and this construction also ®gured amongst the early usages of the term in Jensen

de Lo pez's corpus.

The embodiment of spatial cognition 37

Page 22: Language, culture and the embodiment of spatial cognitionprojekt.ht.lu.se/fileadmin/user_upload/project/ccs/5_Sinha... · Language, culture and the embodiment ... The embodiment thesis

References

Bartlett, Frederick

1932 Remembering. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Boas, Franz

1966 [1911] Introduction to Handbook of American Indian Languages. Lincoln: University

of Nebraska Press.

Bowerman, Melissa

1996 The origin of children's spatial semantic categories: Cognitive versus

linguistic determinants. In Gumperz, John J. and Stephen C. Levinson

(eds.), Rethinking Linguistic Relativity. Cambridge: Cambridge University

Press, 145±176.

Bruner, Jerome

1966 An overview. In J. S. Bruner, R. Olver, and P. Green®eld (eds.), Studies

in Cognitive Growth. New York: Wiley, 319±326.

1990 Acts of Meaning. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Brugman, Claudia

1983 The use of body-part terms as locatives in Chalcatongo Mixtec. Survey

of California and Other Indian Languages 4, 239±290.

Casad, Eugene

1993 `Locations', `paths' and the Cora verb. In Geiger, R. A. and Rudzka-

Ostyn, B. (eds.), Conceptualizations and Mental Processing in Language.

Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter, 593±645.

Casad, Eugene and Ronald Langacker

1985 `Inside' and `outside' in Cora grammar. International Journal of American

Linguistics 51, 247±281.

Choi, Soonya and Melissa Bowerman

1991 Learning to express motion events in English and Korean: The in¯uence

of language-speci®c lexicalization patterns. Cognition 41, 83±121.

Chomsky, Noam

1968 Language and Mind. New York: Harcourt, Brace and World.

Clark, Eve

1973 Non-linguistic strategies and the acquisition of word meanings. Cognition

2, 161±182.

Cromer, Richard

1974 The development of language and cognition: The cognition hypothesis. In

B. Foss (ed.), New Perspectives in Child Development. Harmondsworth:

Penguin, 184±252.

Damasio, Antonio

2000 The Feeling of What Happens: Body and Emotion in the Making of

Consciousness. London: William Heinemann.

Elman, Je�, Elizabeth Bates, Mark Johnson, Annette Karmilo�-Smith, Dominico Parisi,

and Kim Plunkett

1996 Rethinking Innateness: A Connectionist Perspective on Development.

Cambridge, MA: MIT Press/Bradford Books.

Freeman, Norman, Sharon Lloyd, and Chris Sinha

1980 Infant search tasks reveal early concepts of containment and canonical usage

of objects. Cognition 8, 243±262.

38 C. Sinha and K. Jensen de LoÂpez

Page 23: Language, culture and the embodiment of spatial cognitionprojekt.ht.lu.se/fileadmin/user_upload/project/ccs/5_Sinha... · Language, culture and the embodiment ... The embodiment thesis

Freeman, Norman, Chris Sinha, and Stephen Condli�e

1981 Collaboration and confrontation with young children in language compre-

hension testing. In Robinson, W. Peter (ed.), Communication in Development.

London: Academic Press, 63±88.

Gumperz, J. and Stephen Levinson

1996 Rethinking Linguistic Relativity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Heine, Bernd

1997 Cognitive Foundations of Grammar. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Humboldt, Wilhelm von

1988 [1836]On Language: The Diversity of Human Language Structure and its In¯uence

on the Mental Development of Mankind. Cambridge: Cambridge University

Press.

Jensen de Lo pez, Kristine

1998 Organizing space by use of prepositions, body part terms and dispositional

verbs. Paper presented to the Second Conference on Conceptual Structure in

Discourse, Atlanta, June.

1999 The acquisition of Zapotec body part Locatives: A longitudinal case study.

Poster presented at the International Congress in the Acquisition of Child

Language, San Sebastian, July.

Johnson, Christopher

1999 Metaphor vs. con¯ation in the case of polysemy: The case of see. In

Masako Hiraga, Chris Sinha, and Sherman Wilcox (eds.), Cultural,

Psychological and Typological Issues in Cognitive Linguistics. Amsterdam:

Benjamins, 155±169.

Johnson, Mark

1987 The Body in the Mind: The Bodily Basis of Meaning, Imagination and Reason.

Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Lako�, George

1987 Women, Fire and Dangerous Things: What Categories Reveal About the Mind.

Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Lako�, George and Mark Johnson

1999 Philosophy in the Flesh: The Embodied Mind and its Challenge to Western

Thought. New York: Basic Books.

Lee, Penny

1996 The Whorf Theory Complex. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

Levinson, Stephen

1996 Frames of reference and Molyneux's question: Crosslinguistic evidence.

In Bloom, Paul, Mary A. Peterson, Lyn Nadel, and Merrill F. Garret

(eds.), Language and Space. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press/Bradford Books,

109±169.

Lloyd, Sharon, Chris Sinha, and Norman Freeman

1981 Spatial reference systems and the canonicality e�ect in infant search. Journal

of Experimental Child Psychology 32, 1±10.

Lock, Andrew

2000 Phylogenetic time and symbol creation: Where do Zopeds come from?

Culture and Psychology 6, 105±129.

Lucy, John

1992a Language Diversity and Thought: A Reformulation of the Linguistic Relativity

Hypothesis. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

The embodiment of spatial cognition 39

Page 24: Language, culture and the embodiment of spatial cognitionprojekt.ht.lu.se/fileadmin/user_upload/project/ccs/5_Sinha... · Language, culture and the embodiment ... The embodiment thesis

Lucy, John

1992b Grammatical Categories and Cognition: A Case Study of the Linguistic

Relativity Hypothesis. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

MacLaury, Robert

1989 Zapotec body-part locatives: Prototypes and metaphoric extensions.

International Journal of American Linguistics 55, 119±154.

Mandler, Jean

1996 Preverbal representation and language. In Bloom, Paul, Mary A. Peterson,

Lyn Nadel, and Merrill F. Garret (eds.), Language and Space. Cambridge,

MA: MIT Press/Bradford Books, 365±383.

Munro, Pamela and Felipe Lo pez

1999 San Lucas QuiavinõÂ Zapotec Dictionary. UCLA Chicano Studies Research

Center Publications.

Neisser, Ulric

1976 Cognition and Reality: Principles and Implications of Cognitive Psychology.

San Francisco: W. H. Freeman.

Palmer, Gary

1996 Towards a Theory of Cultural Linguistics. Austin: University of Texas Press.

Palmer, Gary and Dorothea Neal Arin

1999 The domain of ancestral spirits in Bantu noun classi®cation. In Masako

Hiraga, Chris Sinha, and Sherman Wilcox (eds.), Cultural, Psychological and

Typological Issues in Cognitive Linguistics. Amsterdam: Benjamins, 25±45.

Pederson, Eric, Eve Danziger, David Wilkins, Stephen Levinson, Sotaro Kita, and Gunter

Senft

1998 Semantic typology and spatial conceptualization. Language 74, 557±589.

Piaget, Jean

1953 The Origin of Intelligence in the Child. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

1963 Le langage et les ope rations intellectuelles. InProbleÁmes de psycholinguistique:

symposium de l'association de psychologie scienti®que de langue francËaise.

Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 51±61.

1972a Insights and Illusions of Philosophy. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

1972b The Principles of Genetic Epistemology. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

Plunkett, Kim and Chris Sinha

1992 Connectionism and developmental theory. British Journal of Developmental

Psychology 10, 209±254.

Slobin, Dan I.

1997 The origins of grammaticizable notions: Beyond the individual mind. In

Slobin, Dan I. (ed.), The Crosslinguistic Study of Language Acquisition,

vol.5: Expanding the Contexts. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence EarlbaumAssociates,

265±323.

Sinha, Chris

1982 Representational development and the structure of action. In Butterworth

George, and Paul Light (eds.), Social Cognition: Studies in the Development

of Understanding. Brighton: Harvester Press, 137±162.

1988 Language and Representation: A Socio-Naturalistic Approach to Human

Development. Hemel Hempstead: Harvester-Wheatsheaf.

1999 Grounding, mapping and acts of meaning. In Janssen, Theo and Gisela

Redeker (eds.), Cognitive Linguistics: Foundations, Scope and Methodology.

Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter, 223±255.

40 C. Sinha and K. Jensen de LoÂpez

Page 25: Language, culture and the embodiment of spatial cognitionprojekt.ht.lu.se/fileadmin/user_upload/project/ccs/5_Sinha... · Language, culture and the embodiment ... The embodiment thesis

Sinha, Chris and Tania Kuteva

1995 Distributed spatial semantics. Nordic Journal of Linguistics 18, 167±199.

Sinha, Chris, Lis Thorseng, Mariko Hayashi, and Kim Plunkett

1999 Spatial language acquisition in Danish, English and Japanese. In Broeder,

Peter and Jaap Murre (eds.), Language and Thought in Development.

TuÈ bingen: Gunter Narr, 95±125.

Shore, Bradd

1996 Culture in Mind: Cognition, culture and the problem of meaning. New York:

Oxford University Press.

TaõÂmy, Len

1985 Lexicalization patterns: Semantic structure in lexical forms. In Shopen, T.

(ed.), Language Typology and Syntactic Description, vol. 3: Grammatical

Categories and the Lexicon. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press,

57±149.

Thorseng, Lis

1997 Acquisition of spatial relational terms in Danish and English: A cognitive

linguistic analysis. Unpublished Ph.D. dissertation, Aarhus University.

Vandeloise, Claude

1991 Spatial Prepositions: A Case Study from French. Chicago: Chicago University

Press.

Vygotsky, Lev

1978 [1930]Mind in Society: The Development of Higher Psychological Processes.

Edited by Michael Cole, Vera John-Steiner, Sylvia Scribner, and Ellen

Souberman. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

1986 Thought and Language. Edited by Alex Kozulin. Cambridge, MA: Harvard

University Press. Wilcox, Stephen and David Palermo

1975 `In', `on' and `under' revisited. Cognition 3, 245±254.

The embodiment of spatial cognition 41


Recommended