+ All Categories
Home > Documents > Pluralism in Historiography a Case Study

Pluralism in Historiography a Case Study

Date post: 07-Jul-2018
Category:
Upload: iwain
View: 216 times
Download: 0 times
Share this document with a friend

of 38

Transcript
  • 8/18/2019 Pluralism in Historiography a Case Study

    1/38

    Pluralism in Historiography: A Case Study of Case Studies1

    Katherina Kinzel

    [Preprint version. An edited version appears in Sauer, Tillman and Raphael

    Scholl (eds.). forthcoming. The Philosophy of Historical Case Studies.

    Boston Studies in the Philosophy and istory of Science. !ordrecht"

    Springer.#

     The story of the Scienti$c Revolution in the %&th and %'thcenturies has een

    told many times. t has een reconstructed in a discontinuous narrative y

    Ale*andre +oyr -ho descried it as a fundamental intellectual

    transformation triumphing in the mathematiation of nature (+oyr %/0&).

    t has een told as an origin story y erert Butter$eld for -hom it mar1s

    the advent of modernity (Butter$eld %/2/). 3ther authors have presented

    the story emphasiing continuities et-een modern scienti$c vie-s and

    medieval and Renaissance 1no-ledge practices. 4or instance, Alistair

    5romie argued that e*perimental science had een practiced $rst y

    medieval natural philosophers (5romie %/06). And 4rances 7ates stressed

    continuities et-een the ermetic85aalist traditions of natural magic and

    scienti$c empiricism (7ates %/92). :ore recently, the prevalence of

    microhistory has led to a destailiation of ig picture narratives, calling

    into ;uestion the very notion of the Scienti$c Revolution (Secord %//6).

  • 8/18/2019 Pluralism in Historiography a Case Study

    2/38

    deologically contested issues li1e these are ound to provo1e

    disagreement. The e*istence of plural narratives of the Scienti$c

    Revolution may simply re=ect the changing ideological evaluations of

    science and its place in society.

    o-ever, -e encounter pluralism in the historiography of science

    not only -hen it comes to large scale historical transformations of great

    political and ideological signi$cance. @ocal historical cases that, at least at

    $rst sight, appear to e ideologically innocuous have met -ith the same

    fate" they have een reconstructed several times, from a variety of

    diEerent vie-points, and they have come to support diEerent philosophical

    conclusions. There e*ist rival case studies of events as local as a speci$c

    measurement procedure, an e*perimental derivation, or an episode of

    theory8choice. 4or e*ample, :ili1anFs oil drop e*periments -hich

    measured the charge of the electron have een reconstructed from

    competing sociological and rationalist perspectives (Barnes, Bloor, and

    enry %//9, %'G20? olton %/&'? 4ran1lin %/'9, %2G%9H). There e*ist

    diverging accounts of the historical fate of :endelFs e*perimentally

    derived la-s of inheritance (for an overvie- see Sapp %//). And the

    victory of @avoisierFs o*ygen8ased over PriestleyFs phlogiston8ased

    theory has een interpreted in light of diEerent philosophical accounts of

    scienti$c change and theory choice Gpluralist, structural8realist, rationalist

    and sociological (5hang H%H? @adyman H%%? :usgrave %/&9? +usch

    forthcoming). n some cases, the various reconstructions of the same

    historical events are compatile and complement each other. But in the

    e*amples mentioned aove, the diEerent case studies are in open con=ict.

     They involve incompatile factual claims, give competing causal

    e*planations, carry opposed epistemic evaluations, tell diEerent narratives

    and reach rival philosophical conclusions.

     This paper deals -ith the situations of con=ict et-een diEerent

    case studies of the same historical episodes. t addresses t-o ;uestions"

    4irst, -hich features of historical reconstruction and representation give

    rise to such con=ictsI Second, ho- can -e assess rival historical case

    studies and restrict historiographical pluralismI Although elieve that my

    ans-ers to these ;uestions apply to historiography in general, focus my

    H

  • 8/18/2019 Pluralism in Historiography a Case Study

    3/38

    discussion on case studies in the history of science and in history and

    philosophy of science (PS).

    n order to ans-er the $rst ;uestion, discuss the interpretative and

    constructive dimension of historiographical methodology. :y account

    highlights the selective and theory8laden character of historical

    representation and argues that the narrative dimension of historiography

    is central for the 1no-ledge that a historical case study can convey. Based

    on this account, analye in detail four case studies paired around t-o

    historical episodes, and the methodological strategies employed in these

    case studies. sho- that disagreement aout historical facts emerges from

    the selective, theory8laden and narrative aspects of historical

    methodology.

     The second ;uestion ans-er y discussing diEerent criteria for

    assessing historical accounts. note a dilemma in the evaluation of

    historical reconstructions. 3n the one hand, there e*ist neutral and almost

    universally accepted evaluation criteria. But these criteria are -ea1. They

    cannot al-ays decide et-een con=icting reconstructions of the same

    historical episodes. 3n the other hand, there are stronger methodological

    criteria that constrain historiographical pluralism more drastically. Alas,

    these strong criteria are often not neutral -ith respect to the sustantial

    theoretical issues at sta1e in situations of con=ict et-een historical

    accounts. Because of this dilemma, argue, -e have to accept some

    degree of pluralism in historiography.H

    :y paper has four parts. n the $rst part, indicate on a general level

    -hich features of historical discourse give rise to pluralism. n the second

    part, present a $ne8grained account of disagreement in historiography y

    analying in detail four historical case studies. n the third part, proceed

    to the prolem of assessing rival case studies and discuss diEerent

    historiographical evaluation criteria. n the fourth part, apply these

    H 5omparale issues arising -ithin the natural sciences have een recentlyaddressed in deates on scienti$c pluralism (5hang H%H? +ellert, @ongino, and>aters H9). Although ac1no-ledge that there may e*ist important parallelset-een pluralism in science and pluralism in historiography, in this paper focuson the latter only. Jote also that my aim in this paper is to provide a descriptiveaccount of pluralism in historiography. do not see1 to ans-er the normative;uestion -hether pluralism is epistemically desirale or not.

    6

  • 8/18/2019 Pluralism in Historiography a Case Study

    4/38

    criteria to the case studies analyed in the second part. The upshot of my

    discussion is that although historiographical pluralism is limited, it cannot

    e completely eradicated.

    1. Sources of Historiographical Pluralism

    >hat is it aout the character of historical representation that enales

    sustantially diEerent retellings of the same eventsI o- are competing

    historical reconstructions possileI Part of the ans-er is that historical

    discourse is a constructive and interpretative endeavor, and that

    historians can dra- on a variety of diEerent methodological strategies

    -hen reconstructing the past. n this section, discuss, on a general and

    astract level, three features of historical discourse that can help to

    understand -hy con=icting accounts of the same events are possile" (i)

    selectivity, (ii) theory8ladenness and (iii) narrativity. claim that these are

    not merely contingent features of historical discourse. n fact, they seem

    necessary. shall discuss each in turn.

    (i Selectivity. @i1e the Borgesian map of the Kmpire that has the sie ofthe Kmpire, and coincides point8to8point -ith its territory, the complete

    historical account is an asurdity. All historical reconstructions are

    selective, and they are selective in three important -ays. 4irst, a historical

    account, unli1e past reality, has a clearly mar1ed eginning and an

    endpoint. 4rom the in$nite series of historical processes and events, the

    historical account selects an episode or case that is identi$ed -ith a $nite

    time8span. Second, once the time8span is determined, the historicalaccount selects some events -ithin that time8span and treats them as

    constitutive of the episode, -hile e*cluding others. Third, of the events

    included, some are highlighted, -hile others are relegated to a

    suordinate status.Selectivity is a necessary feature of all representation. And recent

    discussions of representation in science have analyed in great detail the

    selective choices that structure ho- scienti$c models represent their

    target domain. -ill dra- on these discussions, and in particular on

    2

  • 8/18/2019 Pluralism in Historiography a Case Study

    5/38

  • 8/18/2019 Pluralism in Historiography a Case Study

    6/38

    in line -ith his general aims. The actual selections made are aim8

    dependent.3ther e*amples can e generated -ith ease. f our aim is to e*plain

    historical change then the selection of discontinuous features of the

    historical episode under study, and the isolation of factors that may e

    seen to have caused or motivated these changes is the ovious strategy

    one should go y. f the aim is to create an e*perience of

  • 8/18/2019 Pluralism in Historiography a Case Study

    7/38

    -hich types of sources are relevant for the reconstruction of a given

    episode, as -ell as Oudgments regarding -hich types of sources are

    reliale are made y reference to theoretical ac1ground 1no-ledge.

     Then, after the sources have een chosen, these sources need to e

    interpreted in a consistent manner" the sources need to e related to each

    other? past events, actions and meanings need to e inferred from them?

    relations (possily causal) et-een the derived events need to e

    identi$ed? and the events need to e assigned a certain signi$cance -ith

    respect to each other or -ith respect to the present. And each of these

    interpretative maneuvers relies on theory. :oreover, there is not only an

    up-ards inferential and interpretative process that leads from the sources

    to the facts, ut also a do-n-ards process in the concept8dependent

    identi$cation of historical events. Kach historical event is an event only

    under a description, and hence its identi$cation is only possile if the

    identity conditions for the event are speci$ed" hat the unit8event is depends on the telling of

    itD(Roth %/'', /).

     There are very li1ely many other forms of theory8ladenness in

    historiography. But these considerations suce to indicate ho- theory8

    ladenness can e a source of pluralism" diEerent theoretical assumptions

    and diEerent methodological commitments -ill have conse;uences for the

    selection of relevant sources, for ho- historical events are reconstructed

    from the sources, for ho- they are interpreted, e*plained and evaluated,

    for the individuation of historical events, etc. Since historical facts are

    theory8laden, disagreement is li1ely to emerge et-een historical accounts

    that reconstruct the past on the asis of diEerent theoretical assumptions.

    (iii "arrativity. A third and $nal feature that leads to pluralism is the

    narrative character of historical discourse. The narratological tradition

    -ithin the philosophy of history has long claimed that the peculiar form of

    historical representation G that -hich distinguishes historical

    reconstructions from other types of representational discourse G consists in

    the use of narrative. Rendering past events, states and processes

    intelligile re;uires that a story e told aout them. By ecoming

    &

  • 8/18/2019 Pluralism in Historiography a Case Study

    8/38

    entrenched in a story historical events achieve signi$cance and meaning

    and -hich story is told is relevant for the 1no-ledge a historical account

    can convey.2

    ayden >hite oserved that in order to uild a historical account, the

    series of historical events (the chronicle) has to e molded into a story

    that characteries these events in terms of eginning, transitional phase

    and endpoint(>hite %/&6, 0). And according to >hite, in this process, the

    choice of narrative form or mode of emplotment is crucial. This is ecause

    narratives

  • 8/18/2019 Pluralism in Historiography a Case Study

    9/38

    and the same historical episode can e rendered intelligile in manifold

    -ays y dra-ing on diEerent story types and modes of emplotment.0 

    Aout the same events, many diEerent stories can e told.

     The more general ;uestion that follo-s from the discussion of selectivity,theory8ladenness and narrativity in historical discourse is ho- strong

    pluralism is or needs to e. >hite himself remains some-hat amivalent

    aout the strength of pluralism. n some passages he grants that there are

    epistemic constraints on -hat types of narrative can e plausily told

    aout a speci$c historical episode (>hite %/&', 2&82', 0/). n other

    passages, ho-ever, he suggests that there are not any limits on

    narrativiation? hite %/&6, 266). ere it appears that

    >hite is not only a pluralist, ut also an anything goes relativist for -hom

    there are no epistemic constraints -hatsoever that -ould restrict -hat

    narratives -e can meaningfully and plausily tell.:y o-n pluralist thesis is not that radical. n later sections, -ill

    sho- that there are important epistemic restrictions on the range of

    permissile alternative historical reconstructions. But efore doing so,

    -ant to e*amine historiographical pluralism in actu y studying in detail

    the -ays in -hich rival historical methodologies lead to diEerent accounts

    of past events.

    2. The Structure of isagreement: !our Case Studies

    Pluralism is most interesting, or most controversial, -hen t-o conditions

    otain? namely (a) -hen there e*ist con=icting accounts of the same

    historical episodes, and () -hen it is not ovious -hich of the diEerent

    reconstructions is the correct, ade;uate or most plausile one.

    0 :any aspects of >hiteFs narratological account are deeply prolematic. 3n theone hand, his structuralist ta*onomy of diEerent modes of historical -riting isstatic, arti$cial and irritatingly ahistorical. 3n the other hand, from insights intothe constructive dimension of historiography, >hite dra-s radical conclusionsaout its suOective and $ctional character. share neither >hiteFs structuralistinclinations, nor his radical suOectivism, and -ish to ta1e from his re=ectionsonly the central theses that historical accounts have a narrative structure andthat there can e*ist plural narrative emplotments of the same historical events.

    /

  • 8/18/2019 Pluralism in Historiography a Case Study

    10/38

    n the previous section discussed ho- historiography can ful$ll

    condition (a) and discerned three astract features of historical discourse

    that lead to pluralism. This section e*plores ho- these astract features

    are realied in actual historiographical methodologies. t deals -ith the

    concrete structure of disagreement in four historical case studies" arry

    5ollins and Allan 4ran1linFs rival accounts of the early gravitational

    radiation e*periments and Alan :usgrave and aso1 5hangFs diEerent

    reconstructions of ho- phlogiston theory -as aandoned. K*ploring ho-

    these case studies ful$ll condition (a), try to remain as neutral as possile

    et-een the competing accounts. The prolem of evaluation and the

    ;uestion to -hich e*tent the rival accounts satisfy condition () address

    in later sections.

    structure my analysis of disagreement y introducing t-o levels on -hich

    diEerences et-een rival case studies can e oserved? () the level of

    factual claims, and () the level of methodological strategies. argue that

    diEerences arising on the level of factual claims can e traced to

    diEerences in methodological strategies. t is on this level of

    methodological strategies that the astract features of historiography

    discussed aove unfold their pluralist eEects. As -ill sho- in my analysis

    of the four case studies, the reconstruction of past episodes of science

    involves (i) selective choices, (ii) theory8laden reconstruction procedures

    and (iii) techni;ues of narrative emplotment. !iEerences in selection,

    theory8ladenness and narrativiation give rise to con=icts aout -hat

    e*actly happened in the historical episode under study.

     This is, elieve, a general point aout historiography" factual claims

    in history are al-ays the result of comple* methodological processes and

    these methodological processes al-ays involve selection, theory8

    ladenness and narrativiation. o-ever, it needs to e noted that the case

    studies have chosen elong to the PS conte*t and that each of them

    comes -ith an e*plicit philosophical agenda. t may e argued that case

    studies in general history and in the history of science diEer from those

    produced in PS ecause they are not to the same degree committed to

    e*plicit philosophical doctrines. This is certainly correct. n general history,

    and in professional historiography of science, theory8ladenness does not

    %

  • 8/18/2019 Pluralism in Historiography a Case Study

    11/38

    typically ta1e the form of e*plicit philosophical concepts eing applied to

    the interpretation of the historical material. o-ever, elieve this does

    not ma1e case studies in general history and the historiography of science

    less theory8laden. t only means that the theoretical assumptions that

    structure the reconstruction of the past, and the -ays in -hich they do so,

    are more sutle than they are in PS.

    The #ravity $aves %pisode

    egin my analysis -ith the dispute over the interpretation of the high8=u*

    gravity -aves episode. arry 5ollinsF reconstruction of the early attempts

    to measure gravitational radiation e*perimentally is central to the

    sociology of scienti$c 1no-ledge canon, ecause it highlights the

    relevance of social factors in the closure of scienti$c controversies. Allan

    4ran1lin formulates his o-n account of the episode in direct opposition to

    5ollins, arguing that social factors -ere not necessary for the closure of

    the deate. The historical events oth authors can agree on can e

    summaried as follo-s" &n the late ')*s and early '+*s, oseph $eber

    developed the rst gravitational -ave detectors and claied to have

    ac/uired positive results. &n the years to follo-, other laboratories tried to

    replicate his results -ith slightly di0erent e1periental setups, but they

    did not anage to reproduce his observations. 2y the late '+*s, $eber3s

    clai to have observed high 4u1es of gravitational radiation had lost all

    credibility and -as re5ected by the scientic counity. !espite their

    agreement on these points, 5ollins and 4ran1lin accounts diEer so radically

    that the t-o authors ta1e the case of >eer to support t-o con=icting

    philosophical doctrines. o- is this possileI There are oth ovious and

    sutle diEerences et-een the rival reconstructions.

    (& 6actual clais. 5ollins and 4ran1lin disagree on ho- and -hy >eerFs

    claims -ere reOected. They ma1e diEerent factual claims aout the

    historical episode. 5ollins claims that the availale evidence and rational

    %%

  • 8/18/2019 Pluralism in Historiography a Case Study

    12/38

    arguments underdetermined the decision against >eer, and that,

    eventually, social processes led to the reOection of his results. 4ran1lin

    claims the e*act opposite. According to him, rational delieration -as

    causally sucient for a decision to e reached. Both authors claim that the

    historical material in fact supports their respective vie-s of the relevant

    causal relations. According to 5ollins, the po-erful rhetorical intervention

    of one of >eerFs critics (scientist ) -as decisive in tipping the scales to

    >eerFs disadvantage (5ollins %/'0, /6G/0). 4ran1lin, y contrast, thin1s

    Fs rhetorical attac1 played only a minor role and argues that it -as the

    sheer ;uantity of negative evidence against >eer that eventually led

    scientists to discard his results (4ran1lin %//2, 29'G9/).

    (&& 7ethodological Strategies. To understand ho- these diEerent factual

    claims come aout, -e have to ta1e a loo1 at the diEerent methodological

    strategies that the t-o authors apply. n the follo-ing, -ill argue that

    5ollins and 4ran1lin select diEerent aspects of the past to e represented,

    reconstruct events on the asis of diEerent philosophical assumptions and

    tell diEerent narratives. This accounts for the disagreement et-een them.

    (i Selection. >hen 5ollins reconstructs the scienti$c deates surrounding

    the e*periments, he not only focuses on ho- the scientists -ho attempted

    to replicate >eerFs initial results responded to his claims and arguments.

    e also presents in great detail ho- they responded to each other. And he

    reveals that scientists -ere in severe disagreement as to ho- to interpret

    and e*plain their failures to replicate >eerFs $ndings. They found fault

    not only -ith >eerFs e*perimental setup, ut also -ith each otherFs

    e*perimental strategies (5ollins %/'0, '28'', /8/H). 5ollins selects those

    aspects of the deate that indicate that there -as profound disagreement

    in the scienti$c community.

    But these aspects are almost completely asent from 4ran1linFs

    reconstruction. 4ran1lin presents the arguments in such a -ay that they

    fall into t-o opposed camps" >eer and his critics. The interrelations

    et-een >eerFs critics and their mutual criticisms are not ta1en into

    account. 4ran1lin is ;uite clear that, for him, the situation is one of

    %H

  • 8/18/2019 Pluralism in Historiography a Case Study

    13/38

    agreement rather than disagreement" eerFs critics might

    have disagreed aout the force of particular arguments does not mean

    that they did not agree that >eer -as -rong.D (4ran1lin %//2, 2&H) So

    -hile 5ollins devotes much attention to the various points of disagreement

    et-een >eerFs critics, 4ran1lin selects and highlights points of

    agreement rather than disagreement.

    Another salient diEerence regarding the selection of historical events

    concerns the role of scientist . 5ollins places at a central point in the

    narrative" 4rustrated y the scienti$c communityFs hesitance to reOect

    >eerFs results, -hich he too1 to e mista1en from the eginning, sets

    out to destroy the crediility of >eer and his oservation claims in a

    series of polemical attac1s. n 5ollinsF reconstruction, Fs rhetorical

    intervention constitutes the social cause that tips the scales against >eer

    and leads to the closure of the deate (iid., /68/0).4ran1lin, in contrast, emphasies the continuity of negative results

    that e*isted efore and after Fs intervention. e e*cludes s intervention

    from his account. According to him, it -as the accumulation of negative

    results that led to the eventual reOection of >eerFs claims, not the

    rhetorical intervention of one scientist.5ollins and 4ran1linFs diEerent factual claims are a result of the

    selective choices they ma1e. These choices structure -hich historical

    events and -hich aspects of the scienti$c deates under study are

    included and emphasied in their rival historical reconstructions.

    (ii Theory!ladenness. A asic diEerence et-een the t-o authors concerns

    their handling of the sources. 5ollins e*tends the realm of sources fromthe pulished record to also include intervie-s -ith the scientists involved,

    -hile 4ran1lin puts the emphasis on the pulished material. These

    decisions are informed y theoretical assumptions -hich the authors

    themselves ma1e e*plicit. 5ollins dra-s on intervie-s so as to avoid

    pulication ias (5ollins %//2, 2/'), -hile 4ran1lin elieves the pulished

    record to e more reliale than other sources (4ran1lin %//2, 290).

    :ore comple* forms of theory8ladenness can e oserved in ho- the

    t-o authors interpret the historical material. 5ollin descries the

    %6

  • 8/18/2019 Pluralism in Historiography a Case Study

    14/38

    disagreement among >eerFs critics y referring to the concept of the

    e*perimentersF regress. The e*perimentersF regress typically occurs at the

    frontiers of en;uiry -hen ne- phenomena are measured -ith ne-

    e*perimental apparatus. n these situations, ascriptions of -hen the

    apparatus is -or1ing properly hinge on -hether it produces the -anted

    outcome, -hile, at the same time, -hat the correct outcome is ecomes

    de$ned y reference to the ;uality of the e*perimental setup (5ollins

    %/'%, 62? 5ollins %/'0, '2).Because he applies the theoretical concept of the e*perimentersF

    regress to the historical material, he can interpret the situation not only in

    terms of disagreement, ut also in terms of contingency and open8

    endedness. e claims that the historical process could have ta1en a

    diEerent traOectory than it actually did.

    3viously the sheer -eight of negative opinion -as a factor,

    ut given the tractaility, as it -ere, of all the negative

    evidence, it did not have to add up so decisively. There -as a

    -ay of assemling the evidence, noting the =a-s in each

    grain, such that outright reOection of the high =u* claim -as

    not the necessary inference. (iid., /%)

    4ran1lin engages his reconstruction of the historical events -ith a

    philosophical agenda diametrically opposed to 5ollinsF. e see1s to sho-

    that the resolution of the deate -as not contingent, ut the only

    rationally acceptale outcome. e applies the concept of roustness to the

    historical material to argue his point. >hen 5ollins concluded that the

    plurality of interpretative options mar1ed the situation as open8ended and

    contingent, 4ran1lin elieves that the diEerent arguments reinforced one

    another. The fact that a series of slightly diEerent e*perimental setups

    failed to replicate >eerFs claims renders the negative results more

    roust? it strengthens the argument against >eer.Again, the diEerences in factual claims can e seen to rest on

    diEerent theory8laden reconstruction procedures. 5ollins and 4ran1lin

    select diEerent sources and then interpret these sources y reference to

    diEerent theoretical concepts. 5ollins applies the concepts of the

    %2

  • 8/18/2019 Pluralism in Historiography a Case Study

    15/38

    e*perimentersF regress and contingency, -hile 4ran1lin dra-s on the

    concept of roustness.

    (iii "arrative. 4inally, 5ollins and 4ran1lin tell diEerent stories of the

    historical events. The con=icting factual claims they ma1e rest on diEerentnarrative emplotments of the episode. n order to estalish this point,

    propose a slightly unconventional practice of analysis" -ill read the

    historical case studies as one -ould read a novel or a short story and

    apply some asic lessons from literary criticism. This -ill enale me to

    identify the narrative structure of the respective case studies and to sho-

    ho- diEerent narrative structures carry diEerent claims aout the past.

    Proceeding in this manner, 5ollins historical narrative is estdescried as an ironic tragedy. t resemles a tragedy ecause it tells the

    story of a social do-nfall and does so in discontinuous terms. According to

    the literary theorist Jorthrop 4rye, a tragic plot is essentially a story of

    e*clusion in -hich the hero is e*pelled or isolated from his society (4rye

    %/0&, 60G26). The story of >eer, as 5ollins presents it, is such a story"

    >eer is e*cluded y the society to -hich he tries to elong. :oreover,

    the tragic plot is usually discontinuous, characteried y a radical rea1"efore and after 3edipus $nds out that he 1illed his father and married his

    mother, efore and after @ady :aceth dies and :aceth $nally realies

    he has een tric1ed y the -itches. n 5ollinsF narrative the discontinuity is

    Fs intervention. By structuring events in terms of discontinuity the tragic

    plot re=ects the demand for identifying a causally decisive turning point.

    >hat ma1es the tragedy an ironic one is that the hero is not causally

    responsile for his fate. As 4rye e*plains, eerFs do-nfall is

    not a result of him eing in error. >hat happened to him -as at least

    %0

  • 8/18/2019 Pluralism in Historiography a Case Study

    16/38

    partly due to circumstance and the story could -ell have ended diEerently.

    is -as a contingent do-nfall. The historical claims 5ollins defends are

    thus emodied in the narrative structure of the account. 

    Jot surprisingly then, 4ran1linFs narrative is fundamentally diEerent

    from 5ollinsF. t can e read as an adventure story. Adventure stories

    organie time in a strictly serial order. As :i1hail Ba1htin oserves, the

    adventure story is constructed

  • 8/18/2019 Pluralism in Historiography a Case Study

    17/38

    turn to a second e*ample, the 5hemical Revolution. Although this

    historical episode is more comple* than the gravity -aves case, my

    discussion -ill e relatively rief and schematic. discuss and compare

    t-o reconstructions of the episode, Alan :usgraveFs @a1atosian rational

    reconstruction, and aso1 5hangFs attempt to moilie the episode as a

    case in point for normative scienti$c pluralism. ere is -hat oth authors

    can agree to have ta1en place in the 5hemical Revolution" The heyday of

     phlogiston!based e1planations of cobustion and calcination occurred

    bet-een '+** and '+*. &n the early '++*s ho-ever, 8ntoine 9avoisier

    began to develop an alternative e1planatory frae-ork that dispensed

    -ith phlogiston and instead postulated the e1istence of another

    substance, naely o1ygen. 2oth the phlogiston and the o1ygen theories

    en5oyed e1planatory and predictive successes, as -ell as deonstrating

    appreciable proble!solving abilities. Ho-ever, both frae-orks also

    faced anoalies and failures. Precise -eight easureents in later

    e1perients favored the o1ygen!based frae-ork. %ventually, phlogiston

    theories -ere abandoned. Beyond this asic agreement, :usgrave and

    5hang oEer rival accounts of the processes through -hich phlogiston8

    ased theories -ere replaced -ith o*ygen ased ones, rival e*planations

    of -hy this occurred and competing epistemic evaluations of the

    rationality and legitimacy of the victory of o*ygen.

    (& 6actual Clais. :usgrave claims that phlogistonism constituted a

    degenerating research program and -as reOected for that reason.

    According to him, the 5hemical Revolution -as a rational process

    (:usgrave %/&9, H0G9). 5hang, y contrast, claims that the phlogiston

    theory -as not clearly inferior to its competitor (5hang H%H, %/GH/), and

    that its potential had not een fully e*hausted at the time of its

    aandonment (id., 26G2'). 4or these reasons, the reOection of phlogiston

    -as a non8rational and premature decision.

    (&& 7ethodological Strategies. As efore, an analysis of methodological

    strategies -ill provide a etter understanding of ho- such diEerent factual

    claims can emerge.

    %&

  • 8/18/2019 Pluralism in Historiography a Case Study

    18/38

    (i Selection. :usgrave and 5hang delineate the episode of the 5hemical

    Revolution in diEerent -ays. T-o aspects of their selective choices are

    particularly salient. 4irst, 5hang situates the reOection of phlogiston theory

    -ithin the roader conte*t of a long8term transformation of epistemic

    practices, the rise of -hat he calls the compositionist system of 5hemistry.

    According to 5hang, the reOection of phlogiston theory -as not rational in

    itself, ut a mere epiphenomenon of this roader shift (iid., 6982H).

    :usgrave, in contrast, chooses to represent the concrete interactions

    et-een Priestley, 5avendish and @avoisier, ut he e*cludes long8term

    transformations in 5hemistsF practices from his account.

    Second, 5hang chooses to represent not only the actual historical

    events, ut also -hat could have ecome of phlogiston theory, had it not

    een aandoned. e presents a counterfactual history that phlogiston

    theory could have fostered scienti$c progress had it een retained. n this

    -ays, the counterfactual history ecomes part of the episode under study.

    t is y including the roader conte*t of epistemic transformations in

    5hemistry and the counterfactual ene$ts of phlogiston that 5hang can

    claim the reOection of phlogiston theory to have een non8rational and

    premature. :usgrave and 5hangFs diEerent verdicts on the rationality of

    the 5hemical Revolution are underpinned y the diEerent selective choices

    they ma1e.

    (ii Theory!ladenness. A fundamental diEerence et-een :usgrave and

    5hangFs reconstructions concerns temporality. :usgrave reconstructs the

    development of the phlogistonist and o*ygenist rivals diachronically,

    distinguishing et-een diEerent successor versions of the theories. e

    applies @a1atosF conception of competing research programs to the

    historical material? and a @a1atosian research program consists in a

    diachronic series of successor versions of a theory.:usgrave also uses the concept of progressive and degenerating

    research programs to evaluate the rivals. n his interpretation, oth

    programs -ere successful efore %&&, and it -as only et-een %&& and

    %&'0 that @avoisierFs o*ygen theory egan to outperform the phlogistonist

    %'

  • 8/18/2019 Pluralism in Historiography a Case Study

    19/38

    program of Priestley and 5avendish. !uring that time span, the o*ygen

    program developed in a coherent manner, according to :usgrave, each

    ne- version mar1ed an increase in predictive po-er and theoretical

    gro-th. The program -as progressive. The phlogiston program, in

    contrast, -as confronted -ith increasing diculties and degenerated

    (:usgrave %/&9, H0). This evaluation then allo-s for the verdict that the

    reOection of the phlogistonist e*planations -as entirely rational" chemists

    at the time realied that the phlogiston8ased system -as degenerating

    and changed their allegiances.5hang reaches a very diEerent verdict. This is possile primarily

    ecause his reconstruction is systematic rather than temporal. 5hang does

    not recount the successive steps in -hich the t-o theories developed. e

    applies a diEerent concept to the historical material, reconstructing the

    rivals as holistically understood systems of practice. e analyses static

    and systematic features of the phlogistonist and o*ygenist approaches,

    listing the ;uestions the t-o systems addressed, the prolems they found

    signi$cant and the epistemic values they emodied (5hang H%H, %/GH').5omparing the t-o systems, 5hang applies the concept of

    methodological incommensuraility. According to his interpretation, othsystems -ere ale to solve the prolems -hich they considered important

    in a manner that satis$ed the epistemic values that they adhered to.

    t seems clear that each of the o*ygenist and phlogistonist

    systems had its o-n merits and diculties, and that there

    -ere diEerent standards according to -hich one or the other

    -as etter supported y empirical evidence. [# [B#oth

    systems -ere partially successful in their attempts to attain

    -orth-hile goals and [# there -as no reason to clearly favor

    one over the other. (id., H/)

    As in the aove e*ample, -e can oserve ho- diEerences in the

    theoretical assumptions that guide the historical interpretation translate

    into diEerent factual claims" :usgrave engages in a diachronic

    reconstruction and interprets the situation in terms of @a1atosian

    con$rmation theory, using the concept of research programs. 3n this asis

    %/

  • 8/18/2019 Pluralism in Historiography a Case Study

    20/38

    he reaches the conclusion that the 5hemical Revolution -as a rational

    process. 5hang, in contrast, interprets the situation in terms of the

    theoretical concept of methodological incommensuraility and $nds that

    the decision -as not rational.

    (iii "arrative. As in the e*ample aove, the historical claims are also

    rought across y the -ay the story is told. :usgraveFs historical account

    is -ell descried as a comedy. n a comedy, according to 4rye, the

    complications, plot t-ists and revelations that the hero has to live through

    efore succeeding are more important in determining the course of events

    than the moral or intellectual ;ualities of the characters(4rye %/0&, %&).

     Uust li1e a comedy, :usgraveFs narrative is driven not y the intentional

    action of the characters, ut y une*pected plot t-ists. 4rom the moment

    that @avoisierFs research program enters the stage, -e are confronted -ith

    a series of sudden and une*pected changes of fate, some of -hich reveal

    a deep historical irony. Repeatedly, @avoisierFs opponents are also his

    helpers. They provide the insights -hich enale @avoisier to verify his

    prediction (of -hat -ould later e called o*ygen), and later, to solve the

    anomalies that troule his o*ygen program (:usgrave %/&9, %/2, HG%).

     The comic emplotment in terms of une*pected plot t-ists accords -ith

    :usgraveFs interpretation of the episode as rational. Scienti$c rationality

    e*erts itself in the narrative as a egelian

  • 8/18/2019 Pluralism in Historiography a Case Study

    21/38

    prematurely deceased hero, 5hangFs narrative mourns unrealied

    possiilities. t conOures up an image of -hat could have ecome of the

    deceased had they not passed a-ay and see1s to estalish that

    phlogiston, in line -ith 5hangFs normative pluralist agenda, should not

    have een aandoned. To prove this point, 5hang engages in

    counterfactual history aout -hat might have happened had phlogiston

    theory een maintained (iid., 2H80). This counterfactual imagination

    enales the Oudgment that the death of phlogiston -as not only not

    rationally -arranted (and in this sense unOust) ut also premature if

    measured against the possiilities for innovation, development and

    discovery that it entailed. The elegiac practices of emoaning and praising

    the deceased $t 5hangFs evaluation of the situation li1e a glove.

    aving provided a detailed analysis of selected historical case studies,

    hope to have made plausile t-o points. The $rst point is that there is not

    one unprolematic -ay of deriving historical facts from the sources.

    Rather, historians engage in comple* methodological strategies in order to

    reconstruct, interpret, evaluate and e*plain past events, and the

    methodological strategies of historiography involve selective choices,

    theory8laden interpretations and narrative emplotments.Second, hope to have sho-n that diEerences arising on the level of

    factual claims can e traced to diEerences in methodological strategies.

    >hich selections are made -hen reconstructing historical happenings,

    -hich theoretical assumptions guide the interpretation and evaluation of

    past events, -hich narratives structure the historical material has

    conse;uences for -hat factual claims a historical account can reach. Liven

    these features of historiography, the e*istence of severe disagreement

    et-een case studies of the same episodes does not appear surprising.

    ". #$aluating Historical Accounts

    n my analysis aove, tried to stay as neutral as possile et-een the

    rival historical accounts, and did not present one side of the con=ict as

    more plausile or etter -arranted than the other. n this section, turn to

    H%

  • 8/18/2019 Pluralism in Historiography a Case Study

    22/38

    the prolem of -hether and ho- -e can assess historical case studies and

    settle con=icts such as those discussed.As stated efore, historiographical pluralism is most interesting if (a)

    it occurs et-een con=icting historical accounts, and () the alternatives

    on oEer are plausile to roughly similar e*tents. The ;uestion as to

    -hether and ho- -e can assess competing historical case studies is of

    central importance to historiographical pluralism, ecause it ears on

    condition (), the issue of comparative plausiility" the stronger our

    grounds for assessing case studies and for deciding et-een rival

    reconstructions, the -ea1er is our pluralist scenario. f -e can al-ays

    reach une;uivocal decisions et-een competing accounts, then there is

    no room for pluralism in historiography. 3r at least the more controversial

    forms of pluralism that occur et-een incompatile and con=icting

    reconstructions -ill e ruled out. 3n the other e*treme, if -e can never

     Oudge -hich of t-o or more alternative accounts is the most plausile,

    then -e are confronted -ith a situation of e*treme pluralism, or even

    anything8goes relativism.:y o-n approach ta1es a middle position et-een these t-o

    e*tremes. argue that there indeed are epistemic considerations thatallo- for an evaluation of competing historical case studies. These

    considerations place restrictions on the space of permissile alternatives

    and hence restrict pluralism. o-ever, they are not strong enough to

    al-ays yield an une;uivocal verdict as to -hich of t-o or more competing

    reconstructions to prefer. n some cases, a neutral decision et-een rival

    accounts may not e possile. n order to ma1e my point, egin y

    considering -hat types of epistemic considerations -e can dra- on inorder to evaluate historical case studies. distinguish et-een (α) asic

    and (β) comple* evaluation criteria. Then proceed to evaluating the

    aove discussed case studies in terms of these considerations.

    ( α   2asic criteria. >hen historians and philosophers of science discuss the

    merits of diEerent historical reconstructions and case studies, their

    HH

  • 8/18/2019 Pluralism in Historiography a Case Study

    23/38

    evaluation criteria often remain implicit.9 o-ever, there seem to e*ist a

    fe- rough and ready rules that one can dra- on -hen assessing the

    ;uality of a historical reconstruction. Some of them are related to the

    practices of source criticism (ho- reliale are the sources used, ho- -ell

    are the 1no-n sources covered, and ho- varied is the evidence citedI).

    3thers concern the composition of the historiographical te*t itself (is the

    historical argument consistent and intelligileI). 7et others relate to ho-

    -ell the historical reconstruction $ts -ithin a roader system of 1no-ledge

    (is the historical account consistent -ith accepted, incontrovertile

    ac1ground 1no-ledgeI). Standards regarding source8reliaility and

    source8variance, internal consistency, and consistency -ith accepted

    ac1ground 1no-ledge are relatively uncontroversial and they are

    commonly relied upon even -hen they are not made e*plicit. refer to this

    type of evaluative standards as asic criteria.

     The asic criteria have the advantage of eing relatively neutral -ith

    regards to philosophical con=icts. That is, -hen using them to decide

    et-een con=icting historical accounts, -e can usually e relatively

    certain that -e are not already assuming a point at sta1e in the deate.

    Re;uirements for internal consistency merely raise demands concerning

    the logical or argumentative structure of the historical reconstruction.

    Such demands seem to e neutral in relation to the theoretical

    assumptions that might e at sta1e in a con=ict et-een rival historical

    reconstructions.

    5onsiderations regarding the reliaility, variance and completeness

    of the sources are, as descried aove, not -ithout theoretical

    presuppositions. >hether a historical account has covered the relevant

    sources to a sucient degree and hence is

  • 8/18/2019 Pluralism in Historiography a Case Study

    24/38

    determined since it depends upon the aims and purposes of the historical

    account that dra-s on these sources. Selectivity and the restriction of

    covered sources is legitimate in principle, if it accords -ith and is

    conducive to the aims of the historical account. 5ompleteness only refers

    to the completeness of the sources relevant to the satisfaction of a speci$c

    historiographical aim.

    Jevertheless, a historical account that involves more varied sources

    can e considered more roust than an account that restricts its sources to

    a speci$c type. Also, there may e clear violations of the conte*tually

    understood completeness re;uirement. 4or e*ample, if 1no-n sources that

    -ould e relevant to the historiographical aim ut -hich are not in line

    -ith the argument that the historical account -ishes to carry along are

    e*cluded, then the selective choices may e considered iased. This -ould

    strongly undermine the plausiility of the historical account in ;uestion.

    elieve that although they are conte*t8dependent and theory8laden,

    evidential considerations such as the ones Oust presented can sometimes

    serve as neutral evaluation criteria. At a later point provide an e*ample

    for -hat an evaluation in terms of conte*tually determined source

    completeness can loo1 li1e.

    ( β   Cople1 criteria. But there are also more comple* considerations that

    can e and often are used in the assessment of historical reconstructions.

    5omple* criteria are evaluation standards dra-n from deates aout

    intricate historiographical issues such as conte*tualism, internalism, and

    e*ternalism (are historical events ade;uately conte*tualiedI)?

    hermeneutics, understanding, and translation (are the historical actorsF

    conceptions and understandings faithfully reconstructed and appropriately

    conveyedI)? te*tual interpretation (is the original meaning of the te*t

    restoredI)? present8centeredness (are ac1-ards8proOections,

    anachronisms and >hig8history avoidedI)? historical e*planation (have the

    right causes een identi$ed, has reductionism een avoidedI)? micro8 and

    macrohistory (does the account address the correct level of descriptionI)

    etc. 5omple* criteria, unli1e asic ones, have the advantage that they are

    suOect to e*plicit discussion. They are therefore relatively -ell understood

    H2

  • 8/18/2019 Pluralism in Historiography a Case Study

    25/38

    and usually rendered e*plicit -hen they are used in the evaluation and

    critical assessment of a historical reconstruction.3n the do-nside, unli1e asic ones, comple* criteria are not

    generally agreed upon or uncontroversial. And disagreement regarding

    comple* criteria can arise on at least t-o levels. 4irst, it may not al-ays e

    evident -hether a comple* criterion has een met. 4or e*ample, it is not

    al-ays evident -hether illegitimate ac1-ards proOections and

    anachronisms have een avoided in a given reconstruction, or -hether a

    historical account e*hiits e*planatory po-er. But second, and more

    importantly, the comple* criteria themselves are contested.4or e*ample, in discussions concerning >hig history and present8

    centeredness there is sustantial disagreement regarding theidenti$cation of the e*act vices that result from present8centered

    historiography of science. There is also disagreement concerning -hether

    all or only some speci$c uses of present8day 1no-ledge and categories in

    the interpretation and e*planation of past science are to e avoided

    (Ashplant and >ilson %/''? 5unningham %/''? 5unningham and >illiams

    %//6? Uardine H). :oreover, it has een suggested that the evaluation

    of past 1no-ledge y present8day standards might not al-ays eprolematic (Tosh H6), or at least that it is not as prolematic as other

    practices that have come to e criticied under the heading of present8

    centeredness, for e*ample, a triumphalist siding -ith the -inners of past

    scienti$c deates (5hang H/).Regarding ade;uate levels of analysis and e*planatory po-er, it is

    deated -hether the capacity of the historiography of science to provide

    comprehensile e*planations depends on micro8perspectives. !oes

    historical e*planation need to trace the local and particular causes that

    prompt speci$c historical events or can it e concerned -ith large8scale

    factors and processes as -ellI (4or a useful discussion of the respective

    epistemic capacities of macro8 and microhistorical perspectives see

    Pomata %//'). :ore fundamentally, it is not even universally agreed upon

    that e*planation, and in particular causal e*planation, should e a central

    aim and method in the historiography of science (4or e*ample, the

    relevance of causal e*planations in history has recently een denied y

    !aston and Lalison H&, 62G6&? for critical discussion see +inel H%H).

    H0

  • 8/18/2019 Pluralism in Historiography a Case Study

    26/38

    Apart from not eing generally agreed upon, the comple* methodological

    criteria often are connected -ith theoretical assumptions aout the

    character of science, or aout the relations et-een past and present8day

    1no-ledge. They are connected -ith sustantial philosophical issues and

    hence are seldom neutral -ith regards to philosophical deates. The case is most ovious -ith methodological deates concerning

    ade;uate conte*tualiation. 5learly, in the dispute et-een 5ollins and

    4ran1lin, ;uestions regarding the method of ade;uate conte*tualiation

    are intimately related to -hat is ultimately at sta1e in the con=ict et-een

    them" the social nature of scienti$c decision8ma1ing. The other comple*

    criteria are philosophically laden in a similar manner. :ethodological

    deates over anachronism and >hig8history are related to philosophical

    ;uestions regarding continuity and discontinuity in the history of science,

    scienti$c change and progress. 5onsiderations regarding e*planation and

    understanding in history carry over into philosophical issues concerning

    the relations et-een reasons and causes, scienti$c rationality, and the

    driving forces of theory change. And to the degree that the comple*

    criteria are not independent of philosophical positions and claims, they

    should also not e e*pected to e neutral -ith regards to the theoretical

    issues at sta1e in con=icts et-een rival historical reconstructions. >hen

    -e are relying on a comple* criterion in order to decide et-een

    con=icting historical accounts, -e cannot al-ays e sure that -e are not

    already assuming a point at sta1e in the deate. n some cases, the failure

    of a historical account to satisfy a certain comple* criterion may e more

    indicative of that same criterion eing de$ned in a philosophically invested

    manner, rather than of a neutrally assessale =a- of the account in

    ;uestion.

    %. Constraints on Pluralism

    aving distinguished et-een asic and comple* criteria, -ant to return

    to the four historical case studies analyed earlier in order to evaluate ho-

    -ell they fare -ith respect to the neutral evaluation criteria -e introduced.

    n this analysis, see1 to sustantiate t-o claims. 4irst, asic evaluation

    criteria reduce the space of permissile alternatives and hence restrict

    H9

  • 8/18/2019 Pluralism in Historiography a Case Study

    27/38

    pluralism. But second, the verdicts that -e can reach on their asis are

    relatively -ea1, and in order to reach a more de$nite decision, -e -ould

    have to refer to comple* criteria. egin -ith applying the asic evaluation criterion of internal

    consistency to the competing historical accounts of the 5hemical

    Revolution. The criterion of internal consistency restricts the space of

    permissile alternatives, ecause, of the t-o case studies have

    discussed, only one meets its standard. :usgraveFs account fails the

    consistency re;uirement. t involves a straightfor-ard contradiction in its

    central factual claims. This contradiction emerges as follo-s" At the end of

    the historical narrative, and after having given his presentation of the

    historical development of the t-o competing research programs, :usgrave

    passes the follo-ing verdict on them"

    Bet-een %&& and %&'0 the o*ygen programme clearly

    demonstrated its superiority to phlogistonism" it developed

    coherently and each ne- version -as theoretically and

    empirically progressive, -hereas after %&& the phlogiston

    programme did neither.(:usgrave %/&9, H0)

     This verdict is indispensale for assessing the aandonment of phlogiston8

    ased theories as rationally -arranted. And yet, this verdict does not

    accord -ith claims made earlier in the historical reconstruction. n

    particular, :usgrave had claimed that in %&&0 e*periments spo1e as

    much against @avoisier as they did in his favor (iid., %/9), and that in

    %&'6 Priestley -as having great predictive success -ith his phlogiston

    theory (iid., %//). f these claims are correct, :usgraveFs statement thatafter %&& the phlogiston theory -as starting to degenerate -hile the

    o*ygen theory -as progressing cannot e right. The historical facts he

    cites contradict his interpretation of the situation in terms of progressing

    and degenerating research programs. The claim that the choice for o*ygen

    -as rational y @a1atosian standards appears ill8grounded. 5hangFs

    account is less prolematic in this respect. At least, it does not involve

    historical claims -hich directly contradict each other and hence it passes

    the asic criterion of internal consistency. Applying the asic criterion of

    H&

  • 8/18/2019 Pluralism in Historiography a Case Study

    28/38

    internal consistency to the con=icting reconstructions leads to the

    e*clusion of :usgraveFs case study and hence restricts historiographical

    pluralism.n the dispute et-een 5ollins and 4ran1lin, evidential

    considerations ecome crucial. As mentioned aove, the t-o authors dra-

    on diEerent types of sources. 5ollins goes eyond the pulished sources to

    also include e*tensive intervie-s -ith the scientists involved in the

    episode under consideration. n fact, in the presentation of his historical

    account intervie- e*cerpts are much more prominent than pulished

    material, since the interpretations and arguments surrounding the

    gravitational radiation e*periments are primarily reconstructed on this

    asis. The consideration ehind this strategy is that of circumventing

    pulication ias and gaining insight into the reasoning processes of

    scientists efore they are straightened to $t the format of a scienti$c

     Oournal. 5ollins e*plicitly criticies 4ran1lin for only dra-ing on the

    pulished record. According to 5ollins, the restriction to scienti$c

    pulications only is simply ad historiographical practice (5ollins %//2,

    2/&G//). s 4ran1linFs decision to cover only the pulished sources indeed

    as prolematic as 5ollinsF suggestsI !oes 4ran1lin fail the asic standards

    of completeness and variance of the evidenceI thin1 he does, although the situation is comple* ecause of the

    theory8laden character of source selection. The main prolem -ith

    4ran1linFs account is that it e*cludes a -hole class of 1no-n sources -hich

    -ould in principle e relevant to the historical argument at sta1e. The

    restriction on pulished sources cannot e Ousti$ed on the asis that they

    -ere the only ones availale. 3n the contrary, the original account that4ran1lin -ishes to disprove includes unpulished material. This means that

    4ran1lin dra-s on a suset of the types of sources used in the original

    account. o- a less complete consideration of e*isting sources could e

    etter suited for representing the actual process of scienti$c decision8

    ma1ing remains unclear and -e should at least e s1eptical -hether

    4ran1linFs account passes the completeness re;uirement. o-ever,

    4ran1lin Ousti$es his restriction on source material y contending that the

    arguments that scientists themselves $nd to e the most convincing, the

    H'

  • 8/18/2019 Pluralism in Historiography a Case Study

    29/38

    strongest reasons that they had for accepting or reOecting certain $ndings,

    are most li1ely to e found in the pulications. According to 4ran1lin, the

    pulications display those reasons that scientists eerFs

    oservation claim. To regard the restriction as legitimate in light of this

    aim, one -ould have to suscrie to the thesis that pulished results are

    the est indicators of the rational reasoning processes that rought them

    aout, and that they are etter e;uipped for this tas1 than other types of

    sources, such as intervie-s, unpulished manuscripts, letters and

    noteoo1s. This assumption is almost universally reOected in the historiography

    of science. But perhaps more -orryingly for 4ran1lin, he himself does notconsistently uphold the methodological principle of primarily dra-ing on

    the pulished record. 4or e*ample, in his case study of :illi1anFs oil drop

    e*periments 4ran1lin engages in great detail -ith :illi1anFs noteoo1s in

    order to interpret the formerFs e*perimental Oudgments as rationally

     Ousti$ed (4ran1lin %/'9, %2G%0&). This ma1es the choice of sources for his

    reconstruction of the early gravitational -aves episode seem aritrary,

    rather than methodologically Ousti$ed. Argualy, 5ollinsF account faresetter in this respect. 3ne may point out though that, although 5ollinsF

    sources are more varied than 4ran1linFs, they are still not roust enough,

    since the strong emphasis on intervie-s is not suciently alanced -ith

    other types of source material. n the con=ict et-een 4ran1lin and

    5ollinsF, neutral evaluation criteria favor 5ollinsF reconstruction, ut they

    do so only y a thin margin. This is -here turn to my second claim. Jeutral criteria can decide

    some historiographical con=icts, ut the decisions they yield are relatively

    H/

  • 8/18/2019 Pluralism in Historiography a Case Study

    30/38

    -ea1. A stronger decision could only e reached y dra-ing on some of

    the comple* evaluation criteria. There are t-o reasons -hy asic criteria are -ea1 ariters. 4irst,

    they are only necessary ut not sucient for a historical account to e

    plausile. Therefore they act only as constraints on the space of

    alternatives, ut do not single out one account as the correct or most

    plausile one. To illustrate this point, let us return to the dispute et-een

    :usgrave and 5hang. The application of the internal consistency criterion

    e*cludes :usgraveFs account from the range of legitimate historical

    reconstructions. But of course, this does not turn 5hangFs account into the

    one une;uivocally correct representation of -hat happened in the

    5hemical Revolution. 3n the one hand, internal consistency is not the only

    evaluation criterion -e can dra- upon and there may e many reasons to

    e critical of 5hangFs reconstruction that have nothing to do -ith -hether

    it is internally consistent or not (for t-o recent criticisms of 5hangFs

    account see Blumenthal H%6? +usch forthcoming). 3n the other hand,

    have only considered t-o of the many diEerent and possily con=icting

    reconstructions of the 5hemical Revolution. There e*ist myriad alternative

    retellings of that episode (a comprehensive overvie- of the past 0 years

    of historical -riting aout the 5hemical Revolution can e found in :cKvoy

    H%), and even -ithout having analyed them in detail, contend that at

    least some of them -ill meet the asic criteria. These criteria restrict the

    space of possile alternatives, ut they do not shrin1 it do-n so radically

    that it -ould only include one permissile account. Kven after having

    applied them, there is still room for historiographical pluralism.

     The second reason -hy the asic criteria are -ea1 is that they serveto evaluate only speci$c case studies, ut not more general principles of

    reconstruction, interpretation and narrative emplotment. >hile :usgraveFs

    case study has een reOected on grounds of inconsistency, the :usgrave8

    type of historical analysis has not. nternal consistency is not endemic to a

    speci$c type of historical analysis. 5ould one not tell the story of the

    5hemical Revolution in a similar manner as :usgrave does, y

    reconstructing the diachronic development of phlogistonism and

    o*ygenism as competing research programs and y emplotting historical

    6

  • 8/18/2019 Pluralism in Historiography a Case Study

    31/38

    events in a comic form, ut -ithout repeating his mista1eI >e may not e

    ale to e*press -ith :usgraveFs vigor the conclusion that after %&& the

    o*ygen8ased program -as clearly superior. But -e could proaly still tell

    the story of the success of the o*ygen program as one in -hich scienti$c

    rationality prevailed through comple* plot t-ists.3r thin1 aout the deate et-een 5ollins and 4ran1lin. >e have

    seen that 4ran1linFs reconstruction fails ecause the evidence he adduces

    is insucient. o-ever, -hen analyed the methodological diEerences

    et-een the t-o accounts, argued that the most important diEerences

    do not concern the mere choices of sources, ut rather, ho- historical

    facts are derived from these sources. sho-ed that 5ollins arranges and

    interprets his sources in such a -ay as to highlight disagreement and

    open8endedness, -hereas 4ran1lin reconstructs from his sources a

    historical situation of agreement and roust negative evidence. The fact

    that the set of covered sources is not e*actly coe*tensive in 5ollinsF and

    4ran1linFs reconstructions very li1ely facilitates them reaching diverging

    reconstructions and interpretations. o-ever, is it not at least possile

    that such diverging reconstructions and interpretations could e reached

    even if the same sources -ere usedI :aye 4ran1lin -ould have served

    his point etter had he chosen the same sources as 5ollins, yet interpreted

    them according to his o-n methodological principles. The same seems to

    e true for narrative structure. >hether the story of the early searches for

    gravitational radiation is an inverted adventure story in -hich negative

    evidence piles up or -hether it is a discontinuous tragedy does not seem

    to e completely determined y the availale sources. >e need to at least

    consider the possiility that 4ran1lin could have told his adventure story on

    the asis of the same sources that -ere also used y 5ollins. istorians do

    enOoy some degree of freedom -hen it comes to choosing their

    methodological strategies and forms of narrative emplotment. The asic

    evaluation criteria help to identify the =a-s in speci$c historical

    reconstructions. But they are not strong enough to rule out, on a more

    general level, speci$c methods of interpretation or forms of emplotment as

    clearly illegitimate.

    6%

  • 8/18/2019 Pluralism in Historiography a Case Study

    32/38

    n comparison, the comple* criteria are signi$cantly stronger as

    ariters. 4irst, considerations regarding methodological principles, such as

    conte*tualiation, e*planation and present8centeredness can restrict the

    space of permissile alternatives much more radically than asic criteria

    do. The set of historical accounts of the same episode that are internally

    consistent and that handle the 1no-n evidence in a satisfying manner -ill

    argualy e much larger than the set of historical accounts that, in

    addition to satisfying the asic criteria, are also appropriately

    conte*tualied (according to a speci$c understanding of relevant

    conte*ts), e*hiit e*planatory po-er (according to a speci$c criterion of

    e*planatory po-er), avoid anachronisms (according to a speci$c de$nition

    of anachronism), etc.Second, if -e restrict the range of permissile methodological

    principles, -e have ipso facto restricted the range of permissile types of

    historical reconstruction, not Oust the set of actually e*isting acceptale

    case studies. f -e can sho- that the fault -ith 4ran1linFs reconstruction

    goes eyond his handling of the sources, and that it lies in ho- he uses

    present8day 1no-ledge in the interpretation and evaluation of >eerFs

    arguments, then -e have not only e*cluded 4ran1linFs particular historical

    case study, ut any historical reconstruction that dra-s on similar

    reconstructive and interpretative principles. f -e can sho- that there is

    something -rong -ith the practice of rational reconstruction in :usgraveFs

    account, then -e have not only e*cluded this particular case study, ut

    any account of the 5hemical Revolution that dra-s on a @a1atosian

    conception of scienti$c rationality.

    ence, the comple* methodological evaluation criteria aresigni$cantly stronger than the asic ones. But applying them rings us into

    the center of sustantial philosophical con=icts aout the nature of

    science, the relation et-een past and present 1no-ledge, scienti$c

    rationality, theory change and progress. The comple* criteria are strong,

    ut they are highly controversial and anything ut neutral -ith regards to

    philosophical con=icts.

    Conclusion

    6H

  • 8/18/2019 Pluralism in Historiography a Case Study

    33/38

     There appears to e a dilemma -hen it comes to evaluating historical

    reconstructions. 3n the one hand, there are asic evaluation criteria such

    as source8reliaility, range of the evidence cited and internal consistency.

     These criteria are relatively neutral -ith regards to higher8level theoretical

    and philosophical con=icts. o-ever, these neutral evaluation criteria are

    not very strong. They restrict pluralism ut only to a relatively lo- degree.

    3n the other hand, there are comple* evaluation criteria that are stronger

    than the asic ones and restrict pluralism more radically. But the comple*

    criteria are themselves contested and are seldom neutral -ith regards to

    the fundamental issues that are at sta1e in a con=ict et-een diEerent

    historical reconstructions. Put in a nutshell" neutral criteria are -ea1,

    strong criteria are not neutral. This implies that -e -ill have to live -ith some degree of pluralism

    in historiography, at least if -e -ish our decisions et-een competing

    historical accounts to e grounded in neutral criteria that are shared y

    everyone -ho participates in the deate. This pluralism -ill e limited

    ecause there are at least some neutral considerations that can serve to

    e*clude unacceptale historical accounts. o-ever, even after the clearly

    illegitimate historical reconstructions that do not meet the asic criteria

    have een e*cluded, there can still e plural historical reconstructions of

    the same historical episodes that support diEerent philosophical doctrines.3f course, -e may not -ish to remain neutral in our evaluations of

    historical reconstructions. A convinced social constructivist may -ell $nd

    duious the methodological principles that 4ran1lin employs, the

    interpretations he reaches, as -ell as his narrative strategies. The

    constructivist may -ish to reOect 4ran1linFs historical account on the asisthat it is internalist and present8centered and hence fails those comple*

    methodological criteria that call for a more thorough conte*tualiation and

    historiciation of scienti$c deates. But in doing so, the constructivist has

    assumed some of the points at issue, namely that a reconstruction of the

    deate in terms of its technical contents only is de$cient and that past

    eliefs should not e evaluated y present8day standards. The

    constructivist may have good reasons for holding these vie-s, ut a

    decision et-een con=icting case studies that is ased on them is not a

    66

  • 8/18/2019 Pluralism in Historiography a Case Study

    34/38

    neutral decision. :oiliing comple* criteria in con=icts et-een historical

    accounts reinforces historiographical pluralism rather than eradicating it.

    62

  • 8/18/2019 Pluralism in Historiography a Case Study

    35/38

    &eferences

    Ashplant, T. L., and Adrian >ilson. %/''. higgish (Aout Phlogiston).DCentaurus 0% (2)" H6/G92.

    XXX. H%H. &s $ater H>:? %vidence, Realis and Pluralis. BostonStudies in the Philosophy of Science. !ordrecht et al." Springer.

    5ollins, arry :. %//2.

  • 8/18/2019 Pluralism in Historiography a Case Study

    36/38

    !aston, @orraine, and Peter Lalison. H&. :b5ectivity . Je- 7or1" YoneBoo1s.

    4eldhay, Riv1a. %//2. riting. The5ase of the Scienti$c Revolution.D Science in Conte1t  & (%)" &GH2.

    4ran1lin, Allan. %/'9. The "eglect of %1perient . 5amridge" 5amridgeNniversity Press.

    XXX. %//2.

  • 8/18/2019 Pluralism in Historiography a Case Study

    37/38

    @inderg, !avid 5. %//. hite, ayden. %/&6. 7etahistory. The Historical &agination in"ineteenth!Century %urope. Baltimore, @ondon" Uohn op1ins NniversityPress.

    6&

  • 8/18/2019 Pluralism in Historiography a Case Study

    38/38

    XXX. %/&'.


Recommended