+ All Categories
Home > Documents > The Moral Epistemology of Natural (Virtuous) Systems

The Moral Epistemology of Natural (Virtuous) Systems

Date post: 25-Feb-2016
Category:
Upload: nelly
View: 38 times
Download: 2 times
Share this document with a friend
Description:
The Moral Epistemology of Natural (Virtuous) Systems. Jen Cole Wright Departments of Psychology and Philosophy University of Wyoming. Overview. Two psychological models of moral judgment Piagetian/Kohlbergian model Rationalism (what I’ll call the “MP model”) Problems for the MP model - PowerPoint PPT Presentation
23
The Moral Epistemology of Natural (Virtuous) Systems Jen Cole Wright Departments of Psychology and Philosophy University of Wyoming
Transcript
Page 1: The Moral Epistemology of Natural (Virtuous) Systems

The Moral Epistemology of Natural (Virtuous) Systems

Jen Cole WrightDepartments of Psychology and PhilosophyUniversity of Wyoming

Page 2: The Moral Epistemology of Natural (Virtuous) Systems

Overview

• Two psychological models of moral judgment

• Piagetian/Kohlbergian model – Rationalism (what I’ll call the “MP

model”)• Problems for the MP model• Sentimental-intuitionist model• Worry about normativity• Possible way to address this worry

– Expertise (reliable processes) approach

Page 3: The Moral Epistemology of Natural (Virtuous) Systems

Piagetian/Kohlbergian paradigm

How do we gain moral knowledge?• identification of general moral principles (MPs)

– “All morality consists in a system of rules, and the essence of all morality is to be sought for in the respect which the individual acquires these rules.” (p. 13)

• rational application of MPs to particular situations– “The [moral agent] must be able to reason formally, i.e. he

must have a conscious realization of the rules of reasoning which will enable him to apply them to any case whatsoever, including purely hypothetical cases.” (p. 47)

Page 4: The Moral Epistemology of Natural (Virtuous) Systems

• “To consider ‘socialization’ or the ‘acquisition of values’ as moral education, is to consider the moral principles [moral agents] are developing (or are not developing). It is also to consider the adequacy of these principles in the light of an examined concept of the good and right (the province of moral philosophy) and in the light of knowledge of the moral processes of human development (the province of [moral] psychology).” Kohlberg & Hersh (1977), p. 53-54.

Page 5: The Moral Epistemology of Natural (Virtuous) Systems

Basic assumptions of the MP model

• Moral judgments are typically formed through moral reasoning (i.e. through the application of moral rules to particular situations).

• Particular situation: Fred is lying• MP: Lying is wrong• Judgment: Fred’s behavior is wrong

Page 6: The Moral Epistemology of Natural (Virtuous) Systems

Basic assumptions of the MP model

• Moral judgments are typically formed through moral reasoning (i.e. through the application of moral rules to particular situations).

• Particular situation: Fred is lying• MP: Lying is wrong adequacy of

principles• Judgment: Fred’s behavior is wrong

adequacy of processes

Page 7: The Moral Epistemology of Natural (Virtuous) Systems

Basic assumptions of MP model

• Moral reasoning is the primary cognitive “engine” behind moral development (and the acquisition of moral knowledge).– Man as (approximating) ideal rational

agent Reasoning provides its own

normative constraints.

Page 8: The Moral Epistemology of Natural (Virtuous) Systems

Basic MP model

Perception of

Eliciting Situation

Belief/MP:“A is

wrong”Moral

Judgment: “S is wrong.”

Moral Emotion

(salience/ motivatio

n)

Belief:“S is A”

Moral Action

Moral Reasoning (inferential application of MPs)

Page 9: The Moral Epistemology of Natural (Virtuous) Systems

Challenges for the MP model

• The “adequacy of moral principles”– Province of moral philosophy– VE/Particularist challenge

• The “moral processes” of human judgment– Province of moral (and cognitive) psychology– Empirical challenge

Though both represent important challenges, for this talk I’ll be focusing on the latter.

Page 10: The Moral Epistemology of Natural (Virtuous) Systems

Sentiment-intuitionist challenge• Moral judgments are not (typically) the

product of moral reasoning– Haidt’s research (e.g., disgust issues)– Doris’ recent attack

• Rather, they are the product of emotive intuitions, which are:– engrained (if not innate)– automatic– immediate– “gut” evaluative responses

• While such evaluations are a form of cognition (i.e. they involve an awareness of the rightness/wrongness of things that is, itself, rationally evaluable) they are nonetheless not a form of reasoning.

Page 11: The Moral Epistemology of Natural (Virtuous) Systems

Haidt’s “social-intuitionist” model

• Moral judgment – “is caused by quick moral intuitions and is

followed (when needed) by slow, ex post facto moral reasoning.” (2001, p. 817)

• Moral intuition– “the sudden appearance in consciousness

of a moral judgment, including an affective valence (good-bad, like-dislike), without any conscious awareness of having gone through steps of searching, weighing evidence, or inferring a conclusion.” (2001, p. 818)

Page 12: The Moral Epistemology of Natural (Virtuous) Systems

Basic Sentiment-Intuition model

Perception of

Eliciting Situation

Moral Intuition

(?)

Moral Judgmen

t(“X is

wrong”)Moral

Emotions (dis)

approval

Moral Reasonin

g

Moral Action

Page 13: The Moral Epistemology of Natural (Virtuous) Systems

Basic assumptions

• Moral judgments are (typically) formed on the basis of an immediate (and affect-laden) evaluation to the presence of certain morally-relevant stimuli.

• Our emotive/intuitive processes are the primary cognitive “engine” behind moral development.

Unclear what moral development amounts to.

Page 14: The Moral Epistemology of Natural (Virtuous) Systems

Unclear how to ground normative constraints – how does such a system provide genuine moral knowledge?

• If we take seriously the force of Haidt’s studies– People’s moral judgments look…well,

silly– Highly error-prone, unreliable processes

•Reflections of cultural and evolutionary biases

Page 15: The Moral Epistemology of Natural (Virtuous) Systems

Saving normativity

• Two sticky issues to be resolved:

• First, what sorts of features are our moral judgments responding to (and why should we think they are moral)?– Don’t have time to go into this today (though

it is an important question).

• Second, in what ways are the cognitive/emotive processes reliably “tracking” these features?

Page 16: The Moral Epistemology of Natural (Virtuous) Systems

Second problem first

• Consider alternative accounts of “emotive intuitions”

• Reasoning (“sloppy” or cognitive miser reasoning)– Speed through short-cuts: Heuristics (rules-

of-thumb)– Speed through automaticity: Automatized

inferences

Not really an interesting challenge to the MP model.

Page 17: The Moral Epistemology of Natural (Virtuous) Systems

• Something else (non-inferential?)• Instincts/Innate “modules”• Emotions• Moral sense (reliable processes)

• perception: “Seeing as”• intuition: intellectual (conceptual) “seemings”• “know-how”

Moral judgments as the product of a “moral sense” that tracks morally relevant features in our environment

We perceive the hitting of the child as cruel (it seems cruel).

• Perception-action link (emotionally-laden) Thick moral concepts

Page 18: The Moral Epistemology of Natural (Virtuous) Systems

Reliable processes• Regardless of what moral judgments

are tracking, we still need an adequate account of how they track them.

• Shafer-Landau – moral exemplars– Circularity problem with this approach– Good moral judgments moral

exemplars

• Alternative approach: Draw from accounts of (non-moral) expertise

Page 19: The Moral Epistemology of Natural (Virtuous) Systems

Reliable processes

• Expertise appears to involve (at least) the following two reliable processes:

• Trained perception: – the process by which (complex) patterns

of stimuli, composing or instantiating meaningful features, are directly (non-inferentially) perceived.

• Automatic responsiveness: – the process by which engrained

(automated) motor sets or programs are activated and adapted on-line to appropriately “fit” the situational features that originally activated them.

Page 20: The Moral Epistemology of Natural (Virtuous) Systems

Trained perception

• Eye tracking technology– experts in medicine, art, chess, and

cartography are much more efficient and selective in their eye movements than non-experts

– what they conclude on the basis of their perception is much more accurate

• Birders• Air traffic controllers• Perception of meaningful patterns

– Chunking and inhibition

Page 21: The Moral Epistemology of Natural (Virtuous) Systems

Automated responsiveness• Not rote habitual behaviors• Skilled behavior: flexible, dynamic, adaptable• Golfing studies (experts vs. novices)• Dancing, skiing, and so forth• Direct elicitation of behavior by (relevant)

features in the environment

• “Automaticity in reading, speech, driving, piano playing, skating, or dancing is far more precise and accurate than the same processes would be if they were done with full conscious control.” – Bloom (1986, 74)

Page 22: The Moral Epistemology of Natural (Virtuous) Systems

Conclusion

• A genuine alternative to the MP model– Relying on resources from within the

automaticity/intuitive processes literature• Natural (virtuous) agents

– Develop perceptual processes that reliably pick out meaningful (morally-relevant) features on their environments.

– Develop action-guiding processes that facilitate appropriate responsiveness to those morally relevant features.

Page 23: The Moral Epistemology of Natural (Virtuous) Systems

• expertise model

Perception of

Eliciting Situation

Intuition“Fred’s lying

seems wrong.”

Moral Judgment:

“Fred’s behavior is

wrong”)

Emotion/s (response warranted)

Moral Reasoning

Moral Action

(TP)perceiving

Fred’s behavior as wrong

(AR)


Recommended