+ All Categories
Home > Documents > The Question of Morality in the Context of Faith and...

The Question of Morality in the Context of Faith and...

Date post: 28-Oct-2019
Category:
Upload: others
View: 2 times
Download: 0 times
Share this document with a friend
110
The Question of Morality in the Context of Faith and Reason: Conceptualizing a Missing Essence by Dan Marshall B.A., Simon Fraser University, 1995 Project Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Master of Arts in the Graduate Liberal Studies Program Faculty of Arts and Social Sciences Dan Marshall 2016 SIMON FRASER UNIVERSITY Summer 2016
Transcript

The Question of Morality in the

Context of Faith and Reason:

Conceptualizing a Missing Essence

by

Dan Marshall

B.A., Simon Fraser University, 1995

Project Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of

Master of Arts

in the

Graduate Liberal Studies Program

Faculty of Arts and Social Sciences

Dan Marshall 2016 SIMON FRASER UNIVERSITY

Summer 2016

ii

Approval

Name: Dan Marshall

Degree: Master of Arts

Title: The Question of Morality in the Context of Faith and Reason: Conceptualizing A Missing Essence.

Examining Committee: Chair: Stephen Duguid Professor, Dept. of Humanities and Graduate Liberal Studies Program

Heesoon Bai Senior Supervisor Professor Faculty of Education

Jerry Zaslove Supervisor Professor Emeritus Department of Humanities and Department of English

Ann Chinnery External Examiner Associate Professor Faculty of Education Simon Fraser University

Date Defended/Approved: July 14, 2016

iii

Abstract

This project explores the proposition that at present humanity is faced with a crisis of

moral consciousness due to the weakening of faith in theocentric world views. Secular

reason has failed to replace religion as a primary source of moral authority. The failures

of faith, reason, and codified human rights to provide universal moral authority and

guidance create a unique historical transitional moment and opportunity for a revision of

secular reason as a source of a universalising moral guidance. A set of fundamental

moral principles for individual responsibility has been developed, placing the locus of

moral deliberation and responsible action for moral agency within individuals. The

project examines several moral exemplars that both illustrate and test the moral

principles for their viability and efficacy. Future prospects for the model are discussed.

Keywords: ethics and morality; moral principles; faith; reason; moral agency; individual

moral responsibility; moral exemplars

iv

Acknowledgements

I would like to acknowledge and give special thanks to Dr. Heesoon Bai and Dr. Jerry

Zaslove whose patience, interest, contributions, and help and support contributed

immeasurably to my work on this project. It has been a great pleasure to work with them.

I would also like to acknowledge my Professors: Stephen Duguid with whom I studied

Rousseau before coming to the Graduate Liberal Studies (GLS) program and who

introduced me to GLS, and who also shared the articles of Habermas and Taylor with

me; Michael Kenny, Robin Barrow, and Eleanor Stebner all of whose courses

contributed to a breadth of knowledge that allowed me to make the connections to

attempt this work.

Many thanks to all the people in my cohort and the GLS program who contributed

directly through their challenging ideas and perspectives, or indirectly by making my time

and participation in GLS enjoyable and for becoming part of my life and memories.

I would like to thank Dr. Eleanor Stebner and everyone involved for the 2014 Peace and

the Environment Symposium, and for the opportunity to meet Professor Finney. Thanks

also to Dr. Stebner whose course Liberty and Authority that I found so compelling, and

our shared interest in Peace and Nobel Peace Laureates that are reflected in this work.

Thanks to Professor John Finney who so graciously shared his personal knowledge, and

also his time and willingness to offer assistance and contacts of people who also shared

their personal knowledge and experience of Dr. Rotblat. I am grateful to them all.

I would also like to thank Dr. Janet Giltrow for graciously sharing her time to meet with

me so long ago and to read the Universal Declaration of Human Responsibilities with

me, and for her suggestion that all documents be reviewed as needed.

Special thanks also to my friend Helene Tordjman whom I enjoyed so many discussions

with during the course of my studies, and whose personal experiences, questions and

insights about what I was learning and thinking added much to my experience.

v

Table of Contents

Approval .......................................................................................................................... ii Abstract .......................................................................................................................... iii Acknowledgements ........................................................................................................ iv Table of Contents ............................................................................................................ v

Prologue ……………………………………………………………………........…..........…….1

Chapter 1. Morality in a Post-Secular Age ................................................................ 5 Failure of Morality (A Brief Synopsis) ......................................................... 8 Human Rights - Universal Declaration of Human Rights .......................... 16

Chapter 2. Morality as Universal Fundamental Principles .................................... 21 Universal Declaration of Human Responsibities ...................................... 29

Chapter 3. Testing Moral Principles ........................................................................ 41 Moral Exemplars...................................................................................... 41 Positive Exemplars .................................................................................. 42 Negative Exemplars ................................................................................ 60 Summary Discussion of Exemplars ......................................................... 77 Discussion of Viability .............................................................................. 80

Epilogue ...... ……………………………………………………………………........…..........88 Transitions ............................................................................................................ 88 Future Research and Interests ............................................................................. 90

References... ................................................................................................................ 93

Works Read ……………………………………………………………………........….........102

1

Prologue

I have inherited and lived with the legacy of a history with humanly caused

suffering in the form of the evils of the abuses of people, other species, and the

environment. Knowledge of wars, poverty, poor human relations, self-destructiveness,

and conflict and violence justified by any motives pervaded our awareness. In my

lifetime our consciousness was greatly dominated by the atrocities, ethnocides and

genocides of World War II, and the later war in Vietnam of the 1960’s and 1970’s era.

During this period, too, we knew the Cold War and the terrible threat of annihilation from

nuclear weapons. This remains a threat in current times - perhaps more acutely so.

From an early age after being assigned a topic of War in elementary school for a report,

I chose to interview people who had seen war, and to focus on humour in the war.

Through having people share their personal stories of humour amid devastation, it was

clear from their individual accounts, their pain, and their confidences that war was

inglorious and unlike how the media presented it. Since then, I have had an interest in

peace, and in how morality is essential to peace as intrinsic to it, and to this day compels

my interest in it.

Despite the many people who live morally and well, each new day global news

media report an abundance of every kind of moral failing, human misery, and threats to

humanity. Humanity has a natural urge to survive and to thrive, yet in contrast, people

engage in behaviours that frustrate living contentedly and peaceably, and attaining the

highest thrusts of life. It is incomprehensible that with thousands of years of advances in

knowledge, technological thought and achievement, and scholarship, that little change

2

seems to have occurred away from the sources of moral authority of theocentricism and

reason that have afforded only limited success in the formation and maintenance of civil

societies, and more peaceful and fruitful lives. Several questions arise: Can we assume

there are no solutions to these sufferings? Can we conceive of an understanding of

morality and ways of living that aid in attaining another kind of existence that is more

peaceful and hence more desirable? These are difficult questions, and the subject of

morality and ethics is at once complex, deep, broad, and challenging.

Throughout life I have also been dissatisfied with much of the status quo of

“accepted” beliefs and practices. For example, the notion that there are different races of

people is one that must be denied among many notions that are wrong and may harm

people. Denying this notion for the most part met with either outright dogmatic rejection,

or strong opposition to the views that it was and is simply wrong. Reasoned or logical

arguments typically failed to sway people, and their often impassioned arguments

seemed never to have any substance. But what was wrong?

It is the theme of the relation between reason and passion that is the focus of the

GLS program. In coming to GLS and engaging the Great Texts of humanity, I was

impressed with the fact that they serve as diagnoses of the human condition. They

provide a "trace path" of human consciousness, and the slow and soft evolution of mind

toward betterment. Through a sort-of peeling away the layers of a palimpsest we attempt

to recognize and understand the very essence of human good, and to attempt to

understand why it is so long in being revealed in ways that are widely known to people.

The study of the Great Texts provided a breadth and depth of historical knowledge that

was necessary to provide a context in which to attempt to articulate my long-held

3

assumptions and notions. The GLS program afforded an “overview” of the human

condition from which to attempt to articulate intangibles of human nature and existence

as expressed in the texts. Each of the courses permitted me to advance my knowledge,

and provided connections and a continuity of related pre-existing notions, recurring

themes and adaptations, and new ideas permitting the opportunity to attempt this work.

This project comprises three chapters, each of which examines and develops an

aspect of morality, and proposes alternative conceptions beyond the postsecular age:

Chapter 1: Morality in a Post-secular Age contextualizes this project in postmodernist

and post-secular discourse and discusses failures of moral codes. It begins with a brief

history of our dominant moral codes, and responds to the view that morality from

theocentric sources has declined and secular reason failed to replace it. Notions of civil

and human rights are examined as transitional forms, and as what were intended as

reactions to, and as alternatives to authoritative and totalitarian sources of morality in

20th Century moral discourses. One cause of the failure of secular reason is tentatively

identified and a solution is proposed.

Chapter 2: Morality as Universal Fundamental Principles proposes a conception

of moral principles that is intended to serve as foundational principles of morality that

informs a universal morality that is internally consistent, and anticipates the deficits of

existing moral systems by placing the locus of moral thought within individuals. The

proposed set of moral principles draws upon and draws together the works of Friedrich

Nietzsche, Frans de Waal, and Albert Einstein in order to construct a useful moral

concept. A universalising secular morality is advanced by this conception that

emphasizes the necessity for people to become proactive moral agents, and impels

4

responsibility for moral deliberation and ethical action in a self-reflective way that does

not rely on external authority. A set of guidelines is proposed that is intended to inform

and enable people to become self-responsible in conjunction with the proposed moral

principles and to inculcate an internal locus of moral authority, and to provide concrete

examples of how responsibility may be understood in the context of a universal morality.

Chapter 3: Moral Exemplars is an examination of a sample of individuals for the

presence or absence of the proposed moral principles combined with the notion of

personal responsibility to test whether the proposed conception is viable. Available

empirical evidence in the form of biographical or autobiographical writings is examined in

order to assess whether positive moral exemplars possess and have exercised the

principles and responsibility suggested. Negative exemplars are examined to determine

whether the proposed conceptions were functional for those exemplars, or absent.

Criteria for the success or lack thereof for each category is articulated and discussed.

Discussion of Viability examines the results of the comparisons and contrasts between

exemplars, and investigates whether the proposed model is viable. The chapter closes

with reflections of issues raised in the work, and conclusions about some of the future

challenges to, and prospects for the proposed conception of secular morality.

Epilogue: Transitions provides a discussion of ways and means to advocate the

proposed conception(s) of morality and integrated personal responsibility. I explore

methods of training, schooling, education, and public exposure at local levels, and at

global universalising scales through World Wide Web publication. Future Research and

Interests are discussed and will refer to the ongoing project of investigating the human

condition and possible directions.

5

Chapter 1: Morality in a Post-secular Age

Chapter Summary: This chapter responds to and affirms the premises of the argument

that something is missing for secular reason and by extension, both from and for

theocentric morality. It examines notions of rights for their premises and efficacy, and

suggests a conception of moral principles that universalises to all people independent of

theocentric moral authority. A conception of human responsibilities that supports the

moral principles and works in conjunction with them is proposed.

Morality in a Post-secular Age

If we assume a higher level of species intelligence, it is difficult to understand or

explain the longevity of human conduct that is deemed problematic or immoral from the

evidence that we have not yet understood or solved the difficulties that our conceptions

of morality are intended to address. Prevailing moral codes are arguably problematic in

the context of failing to fulfil their stated aims. For example, generally there are the

arbitrary and relativistic moral prescriptions regulating human behaviour conferred by

varying theocentric belief systems (e.g., Judaism, Hinduism, Christianity, and Islam.)

There are perversions of religious moral codes through which we see acts of

violence or killing arbitrarily committed in the name of God or on the beliefs in divine

command theory variously manifest as sectarian conflicts within religious groups, or

between followers of different faiths. Here a contradiction is either that the “divine” texts

6

are not consistent, cannot necessarily be understood (relating to content, language or

literacy constraints), cannot be followed, are not divine, or are simply not followed; hence

bringing their moral integrity, veridicality and absolute authority into question.

There is the necessity of secular “legal morality” in most nations prescribed as

criminal laws to protect people from the transgressions of others, and to restrain or

punish transgressors. We have the persistence of a vast range of immoral, e.g., cruel,

destructive, violent behaviours, and the abandonment of moral conduct despite having

moral codes to adhere to and follow. In the case of theocentric morality or secular legal

morality both rely on external sources of control and enforcement. As such they are

authority based and authoritarian, typified as “top-down” models that both instruct and

compel people to belief, compliance, and action.

Problems can arise when people may not either know or understand all the

codes, or they have literalist interpretations of religious texts that may result in conflicting

sectarian religious codes, or religious and secular codes coming into conflict. Or, people

may be inhibited in acting morally if the codes conflict with their own ideas or intuitions

and they feel that their “right” moral notions contradict the authoritarian models whether

they actually are right (just) or not. Moreover, if people are compelled to be reliant for

moral instruction or knowledge from external loci, and they do not have texts or people

to refer to when they are alone or are in need of moral knowledge, (or no imperatives

exist) they may have no means by which to discern for themselves what is moral or what

ethical actions to take. This suggests a need for a conception of an internally consistent

internal universal morality that people can query self-referentially to make decisions

autonomously, and to act on their own responsibility.

7

In examining contemporary philosophical discourses and with supporting

evidence from research included in this work, and with the decline of theocentrism which

is argued to have failed as a source of moral authority, along with the failure of secular

reason and notions of human rights to provide adequate moral models or codes, I have

come to the conclusion that humanity is at a transitional moment and epoch in history.

When existing normative models of moralities that purport to inform and guide people on

how to live well and flourish in ways that affirm life and reduce human suffering fail to

fulfil their intended aims - something must change, or something new must emerge in

human consciousness if humanity is to progress and improve its moral standing. I take

as evidence that people recognize, since moral codes and notions of rights exist, that

there is a better way to exist. Otherwise, we would assume our state is normal in the

sense of it being usual, and therefore inevitable; this is unacceptable defeatism.

The question arises, however: Can we respond to the needs of humanity in a

changing moral “landscape” in the 21st Century? I will argue that we can respond in

positive ways that both recognize and use our history, and understand how we can

progress toward a more humane consciousness. Our intellectual and psychological

heritage is one of progression both away from conceptions of existence that legitimized

the abrogation and abnegation of the dignity and decency of people and the destruction

of life, toward an emerging consciousness of the intrinsic value of representing more

peaceful and humane human values that slowly come to fruition. Examples of this are

the realization of the full fundamental value of women, the awareness and inclusion of

minorities, the reduction of notions of “race” and inequality, and the advancements of

science and philosophy that enhance life in medicine and other areas of human

endeavour to name a few.

8

In this project I refer to the works of contemporary philosopher Jürgen Habermas

et al., to situate my ideas in a contemporary discourse that relates to morality. I respond

to the concerns expressed that with the weakening of theocentric morality and the failure

of secular reason to replace theocentric worldviews, that there is a missing essence for

secular reason, and for humanity. I acknowledge and agree with Habermas’ position that

something is missing for reason. Beyond this Habermas’ discourse is examined to

facilitate a divergent position on his reasons for the failure of secular reason, and to

essay an alternative notion of why reason failed. From that, I attempt to build a case for

a workable alternative of a conception of a universalising morality conjoined to reason as

a new paradigm of morality grounded in secular reason.

Failure of Morality (A Brief Synopsis)

Let us start with antiquity. In antiquity as populations increased and began

forming cultures and civilizations, they needed to know the parameters of acceptable

behaviour. They also importantly needed a consensus as to what was unacceptable

behaviour, and how the individual can be prevented or restricted from wrongdoing. In the

era approximately 1000 – 500 BCE the Bible Genesis story emerged (The Old

Testament Hebrew Bible: First book of Moses, Genesis 1)1 as a foundational text of the

Abrahamic religions.2 The Genesis story relates a notion of a monotheistic God that

creates the universe and humanity. In this narrative morality is conferred and explicated

1 The Bible: Authorized King James Version. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press, 2008. Genesis. 3.1

2 The Abrahamic religions are those relating to Abraham, emerging from proto-Judaic traditions and which include Judaism, Christianity, and Islam as three major world religions. Breasted, James Henry. Ancient Time or a History of the Early World, Part 1. (Whitefish, Montana: Kessinger Publishing. 2003) 141.

9

through Mosaic Law in the Bible from God, in which imperatives of right actions and

conceptions and descriptions of sin form moral laws as determinants of wrong thought

and action.3

A single God was considered to be the absolute moral authority governing

human morality, and hence is authoritative and absolute in nature. This theocentric

construct has persisted as the traditional and predominant source of morality until the

early 20th Century. In contemporary times, however, this traditional source of morality

and institutional and social means of maintaining moral conduct is seen as weakening.

As evidence it is noted that more laws,4 more codes, more notions of rights, more

surveillance, more enforcement and more punishments by any method are failing to

moderate human conduct in ways that are implicit in their ethical and moral intentions of

maintaining or engendering morality and ethical action. Failures are evidenced as high

rates of crime5 per capita in populations,6 extensive social problems with greater

complexity,7 and high rates of domestic and international violence as conflicts and wars.8

The 2016 Global Peace Index (GPI)9 shows the world became less peaceful in the last

year, reinforcing the underlying trend of the historic decline in world peace.

3 The first use of the word ‘sin’ as referent to morality is in Genesis. The Bible, Ibid. Gen. 4:6.

4 Includes religious and secular laws, as well as considers the necessity of both to adapt to scientific and technological change which results in challenges to cultural adaptation and assimilation of novel contingencies.

5 U.S. Federal Bureau of Investigation. Crime in the United States 2012. https://www.fbi.gov/about-us/cjis/ucr/crime-in-the-u.s/2011/crime-in-the-u.s.-2011/tables/table-1

6 Government of Canada. Statistics Canada. Crime and Justice. http://www.statcan.gc.ca/dai-quo/ssi/homepage/rel-com/theme2693-eng.htm

7 Ciment, James. ed. Table of contents for Social issues in America: An encyclopedia. http://catdir.loc.gov/catdir/toc/ecip0516/2005018778.html

8 United Nations. United Nations Global Issues. 2016. http://www.un.org/en/globalissues/

9 Of 162 countries indexed, only 10 are not involved in conflict. Institute for Economics and Peace. Global Peace Index. 2016. http://www.visionofhumanity.org/#/page/our-gpi-findings

10

Depending on which research and statistics are employed, whether it is the case

that problems with moral dimensions are not on the rise, but are under-reported or

unreported, remain stable, or are in nominal decline, the fact remains that we have

evidence of a vast amount of humanly caused misery and suffering that our moral codes

have not succeeded in preventing, mitigating, or resolving. These failures are seen in the

inability of the institutions of church or state (faith or reason) to cope with problems, let

alone control, cure, or stop them. Thus, morality that is extrinsic and is authoritarian in

nature and imposed from an external locus is recognized to have failed substantively.

Fast forward, and in recognition of the moral problems, we come into the late

20th Century philosophical and ethical discourses that seek to investigate moral

concerns. Postmodernist theory is a diffuse movement that is claimed to generally argue

for scepticism and distrust toward grand narratives, ideologies, enlightenment rationality,

and absolute truth.10 Theocentric worldviews and theocentric morality are argued to

have lost their impetus during the postmodern era, showing a decline in numbers of

people declaring religious beliefs or affiliations in western populations.11 Charles Taylor,

in his work A Secular Age queries the decline in theocentrism and affirms the change

stating: “One way to put the question that I want to answer here is this: why was it

virtually impossible not to believe in God in, say, 1500 in our Western society, while in

2000 many of us find this not only easy, but even inescapable?”12 The decline in

10

Aylesworth, Gary, "Postmodernism", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2015 Edition), Edward N. Zalta ed. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2015/entries/postmodernism/

11 Pew Research Center. “US Public Becoming Less Religious” Global Attitudes and Trends. 2015. Washington DC. Published 2015/11/03. http://www.pewforum.org/2015/11/03/u-s-public-becoming-less-religious/

12 Taylor, Charles. A Secular Age. (Cambridge, Massachusetts, and London, England. The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. 2007) 27.

11

theocentric/metaphysical beliefs and their force of moral authority derived from God may

be argued in part to be attributable to the many contradictions evident in the Bible. For

one example, it is problematic to be instructed that God states “Thou Shalt not Kill” and

then to find instances in the Bible13 where God explicitly instructs people to kill.14 Further,

the catastrophic events of the early 20th Century of World War I and II, and the economic

depression of the era 1929-1939 appears to have resulted in the questioning and

diminution of faith and adherence to theocentric worldviews when morality failed the

greater populations during those times. These disruptions may arguably have given rise

to postmodernism as a reaction to, or as an expression of the changes in awareness.

In the postmodernist era, with the tendency of postmodernist theorists to regard

grand narratives with scepticism through the process of interrogating theocentric moral

codes we see the inconsistencies embedded in the (moral) imperatives. This likely led to

the weakening of their authority owing to their being recognized as unstable, unreliable,

and corruptible. That is, conflicting moral imperatives cannot lead to definitive objective

moral guidance which is what the authoritative code(s) intended. With these types of

contradictions exposed, and with an evolving desire for moral guidance that is internally

consistent and reliable, secular humanists and postmodernist theorists argued that

secular reason would replace theocentric morality as a more integrally reasoned

humanism. However, it is widely acknowledged that secular reason did not replace

theocentric views, leading to a querying of reason to discover why reason failed.

13

The Bible, Ibid. 1 Samuel 15:3. Now go and smite Amalek, and utterly destroy all that they have, and spare them not; but slay both man and woman, infant and suckling, ox and sheep, camel and ass.

14 It is beyond the scope of this work, however, most; if not all, religious texts show evidence of such irreconcilable contradictions.

12

Jürgen Habermas, in An Awareness of What Is Missing: Faith and Reason in a

Post-Secular Age argues that something is missing for humanity. For Habermas the

question is specifically to ask what is missing for secular reason in that it was assumed

to replace religions as a source of morality, but he acknowledges this has failed to occur.

He argues that “what is missing” for secular reason is the symbols and images that

religion has and which serve as a basis of attachment, or of solidarity. Habermas states:

Practical reason provides justifications for the universalistic and

egalitarian concept of morality and law which shaped the freedom of the

individual and interpersonal relations in a normatively plausible way.

However, the decision to engage in action based on solidarity when faced

with threats which can be averted only by collective efforts calls for more

than insights into good reasons. Kant wanted to make good this

weakness of rational morality through the assurances of his philosophy of

religion. However, this same strict rational morality explains why

enlightened reason unavoidably loses its grip on the images, preserved

by religion, of the moral whole - of the kingdom of God on earth - as

collectively binding ideals. At the same time practical reason fails to fulfill

its own vocation when it no longer has sufficient strength to awaken, and

to keep awake, in the minds of secular subjects, an awareness of the

violations of solidarity throughout the world, an awareness of what is

missing, of what cries out to heaven.15

Habermas’ argument that something is missing is compelling; however, the notion that

symbols and images preserved by religion of the moral whole are what will suffice for a

collectively binding ideal and moral bearing does not address the concerns about, and

the need to have a universalising secular basis for morality that can bind people together

15

Habermas, Jürgen, et al. An Awareness of What Is Missing. Faith and Reason in a Post-Secular Age. trans. Cronin, Ciaran. (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2010.)18-19.

13

in their common humanity. Variants of religions share similar characteristics (of beliefs,

obeisance to a preternatural or metaphysical being, rituals, etc.), but they do not share

the same images, symbols, or other ideals or practices that often see people of different

religions come into conflict when they are in proximity to each other or, with secular state

institutions. Habermas later recognizes this and other problems in the post-secular era:

This touches on conflicts which are currently being triggered around the

world by the unexpected spiritual renewal and by the unsettling political

role of evangelical and fundamentalist religious communities. Apart from

Hindu Nationalism, Islam and Christianity are the main sources of this

disturbance. From the standpoint of their geographical expansion, the

winners are not the nationally organized religious communities, such as

the Protestant Churches in Germany and Britain, but the Catholic world

Church and, above all, the Evangelicals and the Muslims with their

decentralized networks and globally operating movements. . . . The

resurgence is going hand-in-hand with an increase of the conflicts

between different religious groups and denominations. Even though many

of these conflicts have different origins, they become inflamed when they

are codified in religions terms.16

Here Habermas cites the unexpected renewal of religions, which raises the question as

to why this might occur, which he does not discuss.17 One possible explanation is to

speculate that with theocentrism on the wane and with secular reason failing to replace

it, that what has occurred (but there is no empirical evidence to support) is that when

populations are faced with a loss of beliefs that provide homeostasis, they need

16

Habermas, Ibid., 19. 17

There are questions as to what is meant by “spiritual” and what is meant by “religious” with there being significant differences in understandings and practices. Bender, Courtney. “Religion and Spirituality: History, Discourse, Measurement.” Social Science Research Council. Jan 24, 2007. http://religion.ssrc.org/reforum/Bender.pdf

14

something to replace them. In this case, secular reason was expected to be what people

could transition to but it was insubstantial – missing something. Stasis can become

threatened when there is a significant loss of the familiar, and there is nothing to replace

it giving rise to strong reactions evidenced as fundamentalism and evangelism. If there is

fear and uncertainty, or fear of uncertainty, and people are threatened or cannot

formulate or transition to new directions that can provide stasis, they are unlikely

abandon the known or to risk the unknown.

Therefore, it may be that with the failure of secular reason the instability caused

by a vacuum of stasis has given rise to the resurgence of religiosity as a return to the

known and familiar. Moreover, it may be that religious resurgence, if it exists, is in part

owing to the upheavals caused by conflicts that see people displaced from their

homelands and roots. This is symptomatic of the failures of both theocentric morality and

secular morality that conflicts persist to create these conditions. Another question is

about whether there is actually a resurgence of religion as Habermas claims (he does

not cite sources) or whether what is taken for resurgence is partially explained by

population growth and the rise of religion(s) by volume rather than only as revivalism.18

A correlative and important concern is that with increasing populations and

migration owing to global conflicts and economic factors combined with the politicization

of religion(s) - that nations and governments are undergoing radical transformations as

competing interests intensify, and conflicts increase as varying groups intersect and

attempt to assert dominance. Moreover, various religions hold differing moral

18 Pew Research Center. “The Future of World Religions: Population Growth Projections, 2010-

2050” Demographic Study. 2015. Washington DC. Published 2015/04/03. http://www.pewforum.org/2015/04/02/religious-projections-2010-2050/

15

conceptions, hence challenging the capacities of people of varying religions to find

common moral standings and reduce conflicts. The problem of moral relativism is stated

“that there are deep and widespread moral disagreements and a metaethical thesis that

the truth or justification of moral judgments is not absolute, but relative to some group of

persons.”19 What this means is that moral conceptions are not anchored in a single

unifying conception that universalises to all people in an increasingly globalized world.

In view of the fact that there are no images or symbols common to religions,

images and symbols therefore cannot provide a unifying ideal that can motivate

collective action that would lend support to secular reason as Habermas claims. This

means Habermas’ notion of conjoining the images and symbols of religion(s) as “the

kingdom of God” 20 to secular reason is arguably a searching attempt to enhance reason

as a unifying and universalising basis for morality that can mobilize to meet threats in the

post post-secular era.21 This does not address the concern that the transition to secular

reason seeks to eliminate threats from any quarter entirely. This is noted since, as

Habermas points out, the prescient threats often come from or through religions in the

first instance. These manifold factors contribute to understanding the failures of both

theocentrism, and for the artefacts of religion to complete and support secular reason.

With the failure of religions to retain their grip as a source of moral authority22 in

response to historical eventualities and contemporary concerns, and without secular 19

Gowans, Chris, "Moral Relativism", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2012 Edition), Edward N. Zalta ed. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2012/entries/moral-relativism

20 Habermas, Ibid. 19.

21 Post postsecular is a term used that refers to the transition from the postsecular age in which secular reason did not take hold and there was a resurgence of religions, and as a term to refer the next age which may be called something different but is not at this time.

22 Resurgence or population growth does not equate to retained authority or moral ascendancy.

16

reason having been established as an independent, self-referential, internally consistent,

coherent, and non-authoritarian source of morality that eliminates threats while

concomitantly supporting life – there is a missing essence to be discovered.

Human Rights – Universal Declaration of Human Rights

In the mid-20th Century another transition away from traditional authoritative

moral codes came in the form of the creation of notions of civil and human rights.

Codified human rights are arguably our best moral codes insofar as that they tend to be

proactive in affirming and supporting fundamentals of human existence (survival) and

positive intrinsic human value. Human rights are typified and termed as “natural rights,”

rights that we are argued to possess merely by the fact of being alive. As a pre-eminent

manifesto of human rights, The United Nations Universal Declaration of Human Rights

(UDHR) 23 is a secularized expression of the urge of humanity to seek alternative ways to

view itself, and to create an alternate conception of morality through recognizing and

asserting the fundamental natural value and dignity of all people exquisitely.24

The failure of both theocentric and secular morality was evidenced as World

Wars I and II in which the extreme violence of totalitarianism occurred. The UDHR

emerged as a reaction to the degradation of humanity and the evidence of the failure of

theocentric morality to prevail or to intervene that led to the creation of a supranational

governing body that was initially called the League of Nations, which is now called the

23 United Nations. The Universal Declaration of Human Rights. United Nations General Assembly in Paris on 10 December 1948. http://www.un.org/en/universal-declaration-human-rights/

24 United Nations. What are Human Rights? Office of the United Nations High Commissioner for Human Rights (OHCHR). http://www.ohchr.org/EN/Issues/Pages/WhatareHumanRights.aspx

17

United Nations (U.N.). 25 The UDHR as an instrument of the United Nations is arguably

the best moral code for its conceptual universalising notions in asserting, “. . . the

recognition of the inherent dignity and of the equal and inalienable rights of all members

of the human family is the foundation of freedom, justice and peace in the world.” 26

As an example of a 20th Century transitional and transformational moral ideal, Jay

Winter, in his work Human Rights and European Remembrance notes that Eastern and

Western European societies attempted to embrace emerging human rights treaties as a

reaction to WWII where he states: “To some, the Cross represented that transformation;

to others, the Universal Declaration represented a secular story of liberation, one moving

away from both authoritarian rule and war.” 27 In contemporary times with the increase of

internecine and international wars and religious terrorism, the world has seen both a

disarray of civilized societies, and an increase in authoritarian rule in the form of the

invasions of privacy and the loss of freedoms and rights of people to governments

claiming to be compelled to do so in order to prevent terrorism. While rights were argued

and expected to improve the human condition, without the active participation of people

to respect, protect, or enhance the rights they are claimed to have, the impetus to

establish and further a greater conception of morality is brought into question.

Some interlocutors argue that notions of rights have failed entirely. In their work

“Human Rights as a Holistic Concept,” A. Belden Fields and Wolf-Dieter Narr argue that:

25

United Nations. History of the United Nations. https://www.un.org/en/aboutun/history/ 26

United Nations, UDHR. Ibid. 27 Winter, Jay. “Human Rights and European Remembrance.” In Memory and Theory in Eastern

Europe. Uilleam Blacker, Alexander Etkind, Julie Fedor, eds. Palgrave Studies in Cultural and Intellectual History. (US: Palgrave Macmillan. 2013) 57.

18

[t]here is a sense that the world is progressing in a linear direction

toward the universal respect for human rights, or indeed that the

crucial normative issue finally has been determined. The problem is that

all of the momentum toward human rights remains at the level of

ideology. While the rhetoric is not without importance, it is a double-edged

sword; while spiritually uplifting, it also deludes us into accepting a very

rosy picture of a New World Order - a world order of a billion points of

light; a kinder, gentler world order.28

This statement points to the fact that notions of rights, and the UDHR in particular, are

not without detractions and cannot be accepted uncritically, or seen to be an operative

force in the creation of new normative and functional models of morality. As a form of

either idealism or intended pragmatism, the UDHR fails owing to the inversion of its

purpose: It does not establish rights in a positive sense; rather, it seeks to protect people

from the intrusions of authoritarianism and totalitarianism in a reactive sense. The UDHR

has little effect on those who would impose their agendas on other people in order to

exercise control over, or inflict harm on them, as those types of people tend not to care

about any presumed rights of others. Therefore, the rights prescribed in the UDHR

remain purely ideological unless they are actively protected and backed by force of law,

and/or by might (violence). Rights can, and only need to exist in apposition to wrongs;

with no wrongs, there would be no need to assert rights.

This is shown in the text of the UDHR where it states “Whereas it is essential, if

man is not to be compelled to have recourse, as a last resort, to rebellion against

28 Fields, A. Belden, and Narr, Wolf-Dieter. “Human Rights as a Holistic Concept.” Human Rights

Quarterly Vol. 14, No. 1 (Feb., 1992), (pp. 1-20) 1992. (Johns Hopkins University Press) 1.

19

tyranny and oppression, that human rights should be protected by the rule of law.”29 If

notions of freedoms and rights were fundamental and normatively moral, then no need

of defence or prosecution would be necessary, and no force or penalty applied for

purposes of enforcement. Fields and Narr emphasize this point when they ask: “This

universal profession of love for human rights begs some crucial issues. For

example, what do we mean by human rights?” 30 If an entitlement to a right cannot be

defended, or is not defended, the notion of a right is moot, making it, as Fields and Narr

indicate - idealism. In this view there are no such things as rights. Moreover, where the

UDHR proclaims the right to religions, there is no mechanism except by force of secular

law or violence to resolve conflicts that arise out of competing religious claims, hence

creating further conflicts. If people assert rights that abrogate the rights of others, how

can conflicts be resolved other than by negating the rights of one or both parties? From

the standpoint of establishing a normative morality, the notion of rights poses challenges

to their own principles in that they are a form of idealism, and in some cases may require

use of authoritarian application and action - making them similar to authoritarian

theocentric morality.

However, this does not negate notions of rights entirely. Rights exist as a soft

evolution and historical transition in the way humans see themselves: no longer as

subjects or instruments of authorities with group identities, (e.g., national or religious) but

as individuals with yearnings and a need to survive and to thrive. As precursors to and

formative of transitions to more humane conceptions of human existence - codifications

of civil and human rights may be seen as constitutive and representative expressions of

29

United Nations, UDHR. Ibid. 30

Fields and Narr, Ibid., 1.

20

an awakening of human value(s). Here, what other moral codes hold in their intentions

as implicit, notions of rights have made explicit. However, this does not solve the

problems of human conduct and conflict that conceptions of rights and morality are

intended to address. Thus, in conceptions of rights we see another example, along with

that of secular reason, of what is arguably a stalled transitional moment.

Acknowledging the failure of secular reason, Habermas inquires: “Could an

altered perspective on the genealogy of reason rescue postmetaphysical thinking from

this dilemma?” 31 The perspective recognizes, as do notions of rights, the necessary

relation of reason to the absolute value and worth of all humanity as recognized in the

UDHR, and to make that the crucial and only referent of reason and morality. This

perspective, I will argue, is in part what comprises the “missing essence” of secular

reason, and this deficit, in my view, has permitted the corruption and instrumentalization

of reason leading to its failure as a source of moral guidance. Here, we provide reason

with a referent that protects against corruption, and may in part create a substantive and

proactive normative basis for secular reason to form on and to be operative in pluralistic

societies. However, merely conjoining all that the UDHR stipulates as comprising a

conception of human dignity and value as a referent is insufficient to complete a

comprehensive constellation that makes it understandable, and provides ways to effect

it. Hence, in the next chapter, I will propose a set of moral principles linked to personal

responsibility that encourages individuals to internalize this essence of reason as

inextricably bound to human value, and engenders becoming self-reflective, self-

referential, self-aware, and therefore independent and interdependent moral agents.

31

Habermas, Ibid., 19.

21

Chapter 2: Morality as Universal Fundamental

Principles

Chapter Summary: This chapter proposes a basic set of moral principles that seek

to be self-referential for people, and operative independent of external moral

authority. A cornerstone of principles combined with personal responsibility that

universalises to all people is argued to provide a stable and internally consistent

conception of morality.

Morality as Universal Fundamental Principles

I propose that the missing essence of morality in secular reason, in

conjunction with the UDHR, be a set of principles that are internally consistent,

which, if they are understood and adhered to, provide a basis for a positive conception

of morality that can function as a baseline of morality. The principles presented are

expressed through the thoughts and writings of others. However, they are also the

product of a “reverse thinking” process, by which it is meant not that moral principles

were discovered entirely through a creative investigation, but instead that they were

also deduced and realized through a process of questioning and rejecting flawed

notions of morality. Additionally, they are derived from life experiences by being

present when people acted in moral ways that appealed to a personal and often

shared sense of true moral justice, which were recognized as being “true” on a level

that is below the limen of consciousness; not cognized, but felt, recognized, and

understood as being just. They were also in part

22

perceived and recognized through events and instances of injustice in the same way.

No conception of morality can anticipate or codify all aspects of human

behaviour; hence a basic set of principles is proposed that can extrapolate to more

sophisticated conceptions of moral understandings. The principles are intended to

encourage and enable people to reflect and engage in dialectical thought to synthesize

the best moral attitudes and solutions as individual moral agents. Here, the term

“principle” is used in the sense of being a fundamental truth as a basis of reasoning or

action. People are self-impelled to take responsibility for all aspects of morality and

ethical actions: their deliberations, responses, actions, and the consequences. A chief

intention is to link moral reasoning to the tenets of the UDHR, making the intrinsic value

of humanity and all life the salient concern of the moral conception and for reason.

The proposed model defines morality as an active and pragmatic process, as

distinct from systematized or theoretical imperatives, or of external authority that tends to

distance moral agents from an innate sense of moral compass.32 It is intended to inform

and foster a morality that becomes internalised, creating a self-other homeostasis that is

benign, mutually beneficial, and life-affirming. Further, it is intended to provide the basis

for the transition from dependence on existing moral codes to allowing moral

independence and autonomy that consensually universalises to all people. Importantly, it

seeks to function regardless of various categories of differences amongst and across

groups, and may support creating a more peaceful and fruitful existence for humanity.

32 Moral Compass. A natural feeling that makes people know what is right and wrong and how

they should behave. Cambridge Dictionaries online. Cambridge University Press. 2013. http://dictionary.cambridge.org/dictionary/british/moral-compass

23

In this conception, we are not compelled to have or to ascribe to any “collectively

binding ideal”33 of images or symbols. Instead, we are encouraged to behave individually

as self-guided moral agents through combined awareness of the moral principles in

conjunction with the responsibility to do so, which binds people to their own humanity,

and by extension to all humanity in the sense of our humaneness. People thus may all

share a baseline of moral principles that universalise on the strength of their intrinsic

merits as universally good for all, and which will hold appeal based on their survival

value and that they will permit people to flourish if they observe them willingly. That is,

people will recognize the inherent value for their own life, which universalises to others

and is mutually beneficial, and they will be attracted to this conception on its own merits.

This secondarily creates an interdependence of people who can, eventually, learn to

trust and rely on each other to act morally through practice and experience.

The first, and more basic and general of a proposed three-part conception is

adapted from Friedrich Nietzsche’s work Beyond Good and Evil. Nietzsche has argued

that humanity creates truths that are “creative fictions” that aid people in getting through

struggles in living that place the “truths” beyond good and evil (untruth as a condition of

life).34 Here Nietzsche appears to be suggesting that untruths are legitimized by the

challenges of life, and are beyond moral considerations if they are “life-furthering, life-

preserving, species-preserving, perhaps species-rearing.”35 Whether Nietzsche is

sanctioning this view, or merely acknowledging it, is questionable. In any case this view

33

Habermas, Ibid., 19. 34

Nietzsche, Friedrich. Beyond Good and Evil. (New York: Vintage Books, 1966) Ch.1, par. 4, 11. There are varying interpretations of Nietzsche’s philosophy. In this context I intend it to suggest a capacity for people to question and be disabused of false notions that limit or prohibit healthy and life supporting conceptions of life as desired and desirable alternatives, and not to live lies.

35 Ibid.

24

cannot be accepted, for at best it perpetuates human suffering (in the forms that cause

the necessity of untruths), and at worst it legitimizes the immoral causes of untruths.

However, this notion of untruth is useful to provide a comparison and a contrast by which

to provide clarity. In this context, I intend to clarify Nietzsche’s conception to show that

no fictions can comprise a pro-active and “true” life supporting conception of morality

that rejects all conceptions that compromise human flourishing.

People therefore must be prepared to question, and then to self-consciously

relinquish their reactive and negative value-based beliefs - their untruths - to support an

incorruptible conception of morality that refers to the tenets of our fundamental humanity

as denoted in the UDHR, and to anchor to it. The beliefs relinquished must be replaced

by ideas and beliefs that meet the test of being good (moral), defined as those that are in

this explicit sense life-supporting, “life-furthering, life-preserving, species-preserving,

perhaps species-rearing”36 in a non-reactive positive way that takes an absolutist

position for advocating and preserving the life and well-being of all people. I intend this

pro-life conception to include other species, and the environment that all living things

depend on for their existence as a comprehensive life-supporting holism - to the greatest

extent possible. Preservation also implies passive “live-and-let-live” non-interference.

This conception as a baseline of morality proposes a model of reasoned

deliberation, and implicit in his formulation is a no-harm or least-harm model. Implicit

also in the deliberative process that refers to Nietzsche’s cornerstone of morality is the

intersection with the responsibility necessary to being willing and committed to being

36

Ibid.

25

morally aware, responsible, accountable, and to be independent moral agents. I will

argue that this concept seeks to encourage autonomy and to enable people to make

moral decisions without authoritarian codifications that are restrictive, relativistic, or

deprives individuals of the strength of their own moral awareness and capacity for ethical

action. As a universalising conception that is life supporting, Nietzsche’s ideal conjoins

reason, knowledge, values, attitudes, and affect in a universalistic egalitarianism.

Dutch researcher Frans de Waal’s37 work comprises the second part of the three-

part cornerstone of morality proposed here. The interest in using de Waal’s research and

findings pivots on that animal studies traditionally assumed a vicious and selfish “survival

of the fittest” model of existence that did not admit of moral behaviors in animals, or in

humans as animals. De Waal reoriented his assumptions about animals which resulted

in a different view (worldview) that yielded substantially different facts about animal

behavior and morality that inform the assumptions of this work. Here, I am arguing that

people too, as de Waal did with animals, may see themselves in a different context with

different sets of assumptions about their moral capacities, and their abilities to live in a

greater community of humanity in a more natural moral way.

De Waal argues that morality consists of the essential “Two pillars of morality:

Reciprocity-fairness, and Empathy-compassion.” 38 The four constituents of de Waal’s

account of morality are complementary to Nietzsche’s reasoned cornerstone conception 37

Frans de Waal is a primatologist and ethologist. In anticipating objections to using animal research, it should be noted that de Waal’s empirical observational research yields results of positive moral behaviours in animals similar to, or the same as humans. Numerous ethical codes and research on human morality can be resourced that match what de Waal posits.

38 De Waal, Frans. Moral behavior in animals. Video on TED (Filmed Nov 2011. Posted Apr 2012) New York: TED Conferences LLC. 2012. http://www.ted.com/talks/frans_de_waal_do_animals_have_morals.html/

26

insofar as it identifies and relates to, and includes a positive emotional basis for

understanding and affirming the value of individuals in relation to others. De Waal

recognizes that there are other elements of morality; however, he argues that if these

fundamentals are absent, all morality collapses.39 These pillars facilitate the building and

maintenance of human relationships as a socializing process by both encouraging

identification with others, as well as concomitantly reducing perceptions of “otherness”

such as differing beliefs or habits of living.40 De Waal further notes:

It is not hard to recognise the two pillars of human morality in the

behaviour of other animals. These pillars are elegantly summed up in the

golden rule that transcends the world's cultures and religions: "Do unto

others as you would have them do unto you." This unites empathy

(attention to another's feelings) with reciprocity (if others follow the same

rule, you too will be treated well). Human morality as we know it is

unthinkable without empathy and reciprocity.41

Reciprocity and fairness to others are mutually supportive (Golden Rule),42 for

example being seen as encouraging benevolent affects and altruistic intentions manifest

as “right action” attitudes. Reciprocity and fairness are also exquisite expressions of

human justice. Empathy means the ability and willingness to identify with others mentally

(perspective taking) and emotionally as the capacity to recognize the joys and struggles

of life common to all people, and therefore to respect sameness. Compassion is often

39

Ibid. 40

“Habits of living” is coined to encompass socialization, culture, society, spiritual beliefs, nationality, etc. all of which are adaptable or changeable and hence are not defining of a person and cannot subjugate or abrogate their fundamental humanity.

41 De Waal, Frans. "The animal roots of human morality." New Scientist 192, no. 2573 (October 14, 2006) 60-61.

42 The Golden Rule is argued to exist in all the world religions. This suggests a universal understanding of morality that is operative at a level of consciousness below religious belief.

27

manifested as the inclination to help others or to be merciful as pro-social behaviour.

The essence of the conceptions of moral foundations from Nietzsche and de

Waal is that in combination they represent and engender positive emotions and trust

(mutuality) amongst and across groups of people, which in turn creates an interchange

of “self-other” in life supporting ways that both recognize the intrinsic value of individuals,

and reduce or avert tensions in social contexts. In the best case, moral awareness may

arguably result in altruistic behaviours. Humans exist in mutual relationships; the broader

the scope of the relationships people can envisage and accommodate, the greater the

potential for human flourishing – to survive and to thrive.

Albert Einstein in “The Laws of Science and the Laws of Ethics” discussed ethical

axioms relating to survival and to truth statements. In the present project I am viewing

Einstein’s work as the third element of the cornerstone of morality. Here, he attempts to

articulate intangibles of human existence that, I argue, finds a consensus with, and

supports the life affirming statement derived from Nietzsche, and also affirm de Waal’s

pillars of morality insofar as Einstein articulates that at base morality is tied to survival

and emotion, and our urge for life. Each of the four elements has a strong emotional

component - benevolence and justice - or may garner strong emotional reactions if they

are denied or ignored, or assailed. Einstein articulates this as ethical axioms:

For pure logic all axioms are arbitrary, including the axioms of ethics. But

they are by no means arbitrary from a psychological and genetic point of

view. They are derived from our inborn tendencies to avoid pain and

annihilation and from the accumulated emotional reactions of individuals

28

to the behavior of their neighbors.43

Einstein’s observation may be extended from the negative (avoiding pain and

annihilation) to include the positive accumulation of emotional reactions that are the

consequence of being treated in an unfailingly life supporting, moral way. Here I find

support for the argument that it is possible to suggest a non-arbitrary conception of

moral principles. However, while Einstein discusses the notion of ethical axioms, he

does not articulate a conception of how they may be understood, except obliquely. I

have attempted to define an ethical axiom that complements and augments Einstein’s

notion. It seeks to articulate the premises of an ethical axiom as life/moral principles that

explicates and attempts to elucidate what underlies the notions from Nietzsche and de

Waal that may universalise to all people as part of the raison d'être of this work:

An ethical axiom based on the psychologistic notion of “projection-

identification” is proposed. It is conceived of as follows: If I am human and

you are human, and we both have innate drives to survive and to thrive,

then in a fundamental sense we are identical, and we therefore must

identify with each other by virtue of our common humanity. If we interfere

in the physical or psychic existence of another individual with malicious

intent, or to bring about pain and suffering intentionally which necessarily

incurs a negative effect, we violate the principle of our axiom, and by

extension violate ourselves. In this light we can see that by the volitional

incurrence of pain and suffering we consequently reject our own life and

nature: and by extension may be seen to reject life itself.44

43

Einstein, Albert. “The Laws of Science and the Laws of Ethics. (Preface to Phillipp, Frank Relativity. A Richer Truth, 1950, Reprinted in Out of My Later Years, 1950)” Humanist Anthology: From Confucius to Attenborough. Margaret Knight. ed. (New York: Prometheus Books, 1995) 158-160.

44 Marshall, Dan. Female Genital Mutilation, Religious Rights, and Religious Praxis; Humanity Betrayed: Canadian Law as Humane Intervention. July 29, 1998. Unpublished.

29

The conceptions of moral principles offered by Nietzsche and de Waal provide a

fundamental baseline of morality that may effectively articulate what is implicit in the

Golden Rule. Together, the basics of morality from Nietzsche, de Waal, and Einstein

might constitute a “universal morality” that is natural to all people. While it is useful to

propose a conception of basic moral principles and a way to understand and think about

them, a basic set of insights and guidelines as to how to usefully implement them is also

required. Insofar as that a conception of morality that has an internal locus is advanced,

it is necessary to suggest a complementary notion of the responsibilities needed to

support it. A guide of responsibilities that completes a conception of a missing essence

is proposed that I have called the Universal Declaration of Human Responsibilities.

Universal Declaration of Human Responsibilities

The United Nations Declaration of Human Rights45 (UDHR) is notable since while

rights are advocated, there is no inclusion of any concomitant responsibilities to support

them. There are only the assertions of rights and authoritative demands that rights are to

be observed since the assumption is that rights must be backed by laws46 to compel

individuals or associations to act morally. In order that people may mature morally, and

to become disabused of authority/authoritarian models of morality, it is essential that

people take individual responsibility for their moral deliberations and actions in a way

that is self-referential and bound to the moral principles argued for, and in order that all

people may become self-reflective moral agents. Here, I propose a guide to individual 45

United Nations, UDHR. Ibid. 46 United Nations. International Human Rights Law. Office of the United Nations High

Commissioner for Human Rights. (OHCHR) http://www.ohchr.org/en/professionalinterest/Pages/InternationalLaw.aspx

30

responsibility that is intended to bind to the U.N. UDHR and moral principles as a chief

component of a universalising secular morality, and that the three be used conjointly.

The notion of human responsibilities arose very early in my life from observing

the human condition and witnessing an abundance of human misery and suffering. In my

view, it appeared that two possible conditions prevailed: One condition was that people

were not aware of the causes of their suffering, and their faiths (religions) often either

ignored the causes, or served to create as many problems as they purported to

assuage, which suggested on some level a self-fulfilling and self-justifying iterative

constellation. The other condition was noting that people typically avoid moral

responsibility in many situations. In particular, there were those who did wrong things

and claimed an external locus (God or the Devil or another person) made them do it.

Moreover, it is my observation that it was often the case that people would not

take responsibility so that they would not have to “confess” or expose their wrongs and

receive punishments or other consequences. This raised important questions for me

about the legitimacy and usefulness of punishments except to skew morality. Often, too,

it appeared that people simply did not know what constituted a right or wrong action or

the impact, meaning, or consequences of their actions in either the short or long term.

The notion of responsibilities also arose from observing people who refused to accept

the burden of thinking for themselves and stand behind their views and convictions

rather than merely report or abide by the mistaken and often damaging views of others.

For example, the notion of race was often used to rationalize racism and was

often used as a justification for hatred, marginalization of people, or using violence. What

31

is missing from this notion is recognition of the humanity of another person. The

problems and contradictions in such thinking and practices could be shown when people

learned that they might become the object of another’s “racist” views, and they did not

like the realization of their former position, or how their lack of awareness and

knowledge could imperil them, or had limited their sense of their own humanity and

humaneness.

From this kind of reflective example, we may conclude that human beings are

predisposed to have a basic knowledge and an awareness of the essence of morality,

but a fuller articulation and moral cultivation is both needed and wanted. The notion of

individual responsibility that is coupled to a useful conception of morality also provides a

means and the freedom to transcend the ignorance as lack of knowledge that keeps

people helpless and dependent on authoritarian moral codes and institutions, such as

those conferred by church or state. Thus, I would argue that a notion of universalising

individual responsibilities is warranted. On reading the United Declaration of Human

Rights and finding no corresponding manifesto of responsibilities, I thought the solution

was to attempt to write one.

In 1999, while working on my conception of a Universal Declaration of Universal

Responsibilities I did not find any corresponding manifesto on the United Nations web

site related to the UDHR, or other manifestos of human responsibilities written relating to

human rights. Currently, while writing this project manuscript another manifesto of rights

was brought to my attention, and I located others. In examining these manifestos I find

affirmation for my position that a conception of a Universal Declaration of Human

Responsibilities is valid in relation to the UDHR and other notions and manifestos of civil

32

and human rights in that there is a broader consensus and support for all those who

have identified a similar and compelling need. I find this to be encouraging and positive

for all humanity in the context of advancing human concerns and moral consciousness,

and find a great deal of contiguity among the various versions in the intent to advocate

that people must be responsible in order to support conceptions of rights as moral

guides.

As of July 2016 there is no official version that is published on the United Nations

web site in direct conjunction with the UDHR, or as an extension or addendum to it.47 A

version similar to what I have authored is found published on the extended United

Nations organization infrastructure on The Office of the United Nations High

Commissioner for Human Rights (OHCHR) web site and is titled: “Declaration on the

Right and Responsibility of Individuals, Groups and Organs of Society to Promote and

Protect Universally Recognized Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms.” 48

In comparing this U.N. version with what I have formulated, contiguities are seen

in that rights are supported by conceptions of related responsibilities. My conception is

distinguished in that my intention is to create a document that refers to a personal

responsibility that relates most specifically to the conception of secular morality I am

essaying. Further, my conception seeks to provide guides and tests of its own efficacy

that is accessible to a global population. Further distinctions are that the UN conception

47

United Nations, UDHR. Ibid. 48

United Nations. Declaration on the Right and Responsibility of Individuals, Groups and Organs of Society to Promote and Protect Universally Recognized Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms. Adopted by General Assembly resolution 53/144 of 9 December 1998. Office of the United Nations High Commissioner for Human Rights (OHCHR). http://www.ohchr.org/en/professionalinterest/Pages/RightandResponsibility.aspx

33

of responsibilities includes the establishment of domestic and international laws that

support the enforcement of rights, and appears to assume an informed reader and

discusses specific matters of state. My conception is intended to be accessible and

relevant to all people of all ages as a way to engage thinking about morality and

responsibility in novel or unaccustomed ways, and to support the transition in moral

consciousness and secular morality I have advocated. Importantly, Article 7 of the UN

manifesto of rights and responsibilities confers a codified right of others, such as myself

and the others who have composed notions of responsibilities, to create their

conceptions where it is stated “Everyone has the right, individually and in association

with others, to develop and discuss new human rights ideas and principles and to

advocate their acceptance.”49 This statement is an affirming coincidence of creating an

explicit right, which relies on the individual responsibility of people to advocate new

notions of rights and responsibilities for human growth and advancement.

I am fully aware that The Universal Declaration of Human Responsibilities 50 I

have written is a tentative work, and I intend it to be an open document subject to

scrutiny and revision, and to be tested for its value in explicating and advancing what is

proposed in it.51 My intention for it is also that it functions as a type of heuristic “toolbox”

of guides, ideas, tests, and as a means to involve and engage people. Written in the

style of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights, my formulation of a Universal

Declaration of Human Responsibilities is as follows:

49

United Nations. Declaration on the Right and Responsibility of Individuals. Ibid. 50 Marshall, Dan. Universal Declaration of Human Responsibilities: An Addendum to: The United

Nations Universal Declaration of Human Rights. November 9, 1999. Unpublished. 51

The complete work is not included here. The full text contains references that may not be included at this time.

34

1. All human beings are born free and with full rights to life and all that is

necessary to the maintenance of life, and will understand that in

sustaining their own life will bear the responsibility of ensuring that they

understand that the same force compelling their own life is alive in every

person also, and to conduct themselves in respect of that knowledge, and

in recognition and respect of the life of every person.

2. All people bear the responsibility to actively seek to recognize the

fundamental humanity of all people, in all places, and at all times. All

people must understand that such active participation in the interest of

humanity ensures their own place, safety, and trust in a social world.

Trust, decency, dignity and the desire for safety are rightly the generally

universal human experience.

3. For all people in the world to exist in safety from other people requires

that in all instances of conflict people are bound by the responsibility to

their own, and to every other person's right to life to engage, where

possible, in the act of exploring alternative means to resolve the conflicts

present, until such time as each conflict is prevented or resolved

peacefully to the greatest benefit and satisfaction of all humanity.

4. All people are, and will be responsible for the public trust insofar as that

all people have the fundamental human right to exist unmolested, and to

that end must exercise the most just solutions to human conflict,

ignorance, or suffering whenever and wherever a solution is wanted or

needed. It is in this way that humanity will eventually come to learn that

no person is above nor exempt from the responsibility for just action, and

for the highest forms of justice to prevail in all life.

35

5. (1) It is the responsibility of all people to provide or to seek as

necessary guidance free of ambiguity, free of hypocrisy, and free of any

self-serving bias which may harm humanity, or which under scrutiny can

be shown to be false or negates life.

5. (2) It is therefore the responsibility of every individual to seek wise

guidance, and to actively, honestly, and critically think through the implied

consequences of the yield of any such guidance given or received in

order to learn to judge for themselves, and thereby ensure a self-

determined and autonomous knowledge of what constitutes wisdom and

justice, and hence to discern what will or will not be to the benefit of all

humanity. Therefore, it is a responsibility to think for oneself.

6. (1) Wise guidance is desirable when the bias is serving one’s own

healthy self interest in belonging to our greater humanity. In this sense

the self-interest is known to be a healthy and positive self- interest

wherein all humanity is the beneficiary and it is identical with the interests

of humanity at large.

6. (2) It is therefore the responsibility of all people to aspire and adhere to

the authority of wisdom and all autonomous and healthy understandings

of things human, and to aver from accepting illegitimate authority where

there can be negative consequences for humanity either individually or on

the whole.

7. (1) It is the responsibility of every person to support and observe just

laws where just laws exist for the benefit of humanity, until such time as

no laws are deemed necessary.

7. (2) It is the responsibility of every person to refuse and resist unjust

laws as they can wherever unjust laws are imposed upon humanity, to the

fullest extent of their ability to do so.

36

8. Every person will, through the responsible striving to understand their

own humanity, learn and exercise the higher thrusts of life: hope,

compassion, charity, trust, kindness, and Peace in the humane and

humanitarian tradition, and will henceforth strive to pass such

understanding on to others.

9. Every person will strive to understand that in every case seeking the

best for other members of the human species is ultimately in humane

terms identical with seeking the best for oneself.

10. (1) Every person will seek education, wherever possible, of a kind

which develops their greatest human potentials, insofar as that such

education will conform to its precept “to lead out.”

10. (2) An understanding of responsibility in regards to any education will

require that all persons will engage only in educational pursuits and

practices which can clearly be shown to enhance life, healthy emotional

development, friendship, and good will to be directed to others. When all

humanity is engaged thus, conflict abates amongst individuals and across

groups.

11. Every person will recognize that their own fundamental humanity, and

by extension, that the fact of the essential fundamental humanity of all

humanity, is of greater importance than any particular belief or religion or

doctrine. Moreover, by extension, people will understand that the process

of creating beliefs, religions, and doctrines is a process and function of

humanity common to all humanity, and that the individual beliefs do not

admit nor allow any person to disregard the fundamental humanity of any

person or group or persons.

37

12. Every person should carefully examine all communications, directives,

and motivations to belief or to action in order to ensure that all the

intentions, actions, and outcomes of such compelling efforts will serve the

best interest of all humanity, in both the short term and the long term.

13. (1) Every person will engage in or support the responsible and

scrupulous evaluation of all existing documents, constitutions, legislation,

charters, and other forms of human discourse guiding or regulating

human life and action, to ensure that such bodies of work ultimately serve

the humane interests of all humanity equally and without distinction.

13. (2) All social constructs guiding or regulating human life and action

will be continuously re-evaluated to ensure that the emerging broader

global humanitarian social consciousness is reflected in those works.

Inclusions which are outdated or are no longer useful or relevant in a

contemporary context reflecting a developing humane consciousness will

be removed through a due and responsible process, in the interest of all

humanity.

14. No person will deny their responsibility to discover, to experience, and

to advance any or all of that which can be considered to properly be the

responsibility of humanity to humanity. In that each person will strive to

assure the best of humanity through responsible action and experience,

they are participating in humanity realizing itself in the most enlightened

sense.

15. Every person should independently exercise their own powers of

critical judgment, just thought, conceptions of unassailable truths, and

should ultimately come to their own understanding of how best to

understand the concept of responsibility itself in the social context.

38

16. Every person, if having found any of the foregoing to be sound,

practical, and life supporting, will therefore have recognized their own

fundamental humanity in some measure, and in that sense will then

recognize that they properly belong to the greater human family.

17. Every person is bound by individual responsibility to examine,

analyse, and assess all the principles and premises contained in this

statement of The Universal Declaration of Human Responsibilities to

critically test the value for their selves, and for all humanity.

18. Every person, if having found the foregoing Universal Declaration of

Human Responsibilities to have passed the rigors prescribed within it,

must on their own responsibility consider, augment, elucidate, and

contribute any of their expanded conceptions and understandings to

others, to the benefit of all humanity, for the love of humanity, and for life

itself.

In advocating the combining of a basic (or fundamental) set of moral principles

with a conception of personal responsibilities, the intention is to create an intelligible and

cohesive response to the moral problems facing humanity. The two chief factors

involved are to enable people to take responsibility for their own lives by providing a

framework that universalises and generalizes to an existence that has a potential of

achieving a pragmatic optimism, and to suggest a solution to the identified problems of

morality where other conceptions and models are seen to have failed. The second factor

is to encourage and enable people to recognize and understand the necessity of forming

an intention to facilitate their own growth in order to achieve ways of living that are

imaginable, and can be realized. The forming of an intention and the facilitation of

39

growth is concomitant with a process of psychological and emotional maturation of

individuals, and the maturation of civilized societies as part of a natural progression.

In recognizing the necessity of maturity, psychoanalyst Erik Erikson in Childhood

and Society anticipates the transition from dependency on authority to independence

and autonomy. He states that children should undergo a “healthy ego development

which results in an autonomous and integrated personality, and an identity formation that

seems to support an individual’s ego identity as long as he can preserve an element of

deliberate tentativeness of autonomous choice." 52 Erikson’s view echoes that of

Immanuel Kant in his essay “An Answer to the Question: What is Enlightenment?” in

which he wrote:

Enlightenment is man's emergence from his self-imposed immaturity.

Immaturity is the inability to use one's understanding without guidance

from another. This immaturity is self-imposed when its cause lies not in

lack of understanding, but in lack of resolve and courage to use it without

guidance from another. Sapere Aude! [dare to know] "Have courage to

use your own understanding!" - that is the motto of enlightenment.53

While Kant suggests a useful ideal, it is arguably the case that if people could have used

their own understanding in attaining moral enlightenment they would have. However,

given that they did not in everyday life, it is useful to assume that they did not have a

method or a substantive knowledge to facilitate growth. And, attaining maturity is not a

52 Erikson, Erik. Childhood and Society (New York: W.W. Norton & Co., 1985) 286.

53 Kant, Immanuel. “An Answer to the Question: What is Enlightenment?” Konigsberg in Prussia, 30 September 1784 https://www.aub.edu.lb/fas/cvsp/Documents/reading_selections/CVSP 203/Fall 13-14/What is Enlightenment - Immanuel kant.pdf

40

quantum jump; it is a gradual process of development requiring a combination of

information, method, training, education,54 and adequate resources of time and

opportunity. While conditions will vary for people at different times and in different

contexts, and despite individual capacities or limitations of any kind (cognitive,

developmental, emotional, etc.), the attitude for responsibility and agency is crucial.

Joseph Rotblat has stated a case for personal responsibility succinctly in the

context of science and of scientists who take no moral stance or responsibility for their

scientific developments, although his concerns apply to all life:

At the present time, when the distinction between pure and applied

science is largely non-existent, such an amoral attitude is unacceptable.

Indeed, it is – in my opinion – an immoral attitude, because it eschews

personal responsibility for the likely consequences of one’s actions.55

In advocating moral principles and in making a case for the importance of

personal responsibility as a combined model for a direction toward a globalizing moral

orientation for humanity, it is important to include a means whereby we seek aiding

advancing an integrated universalising secular morality. However, any theory must be

put to an empirical test that is suited to its subject and that examines whether the

premises are viable, and whether the theory can be shown to work. To that end, a test of

the proposed principles and responsibility is undertaken next.

54

Educate is from the Latin roots “Educo” and “Educere”, meaning "to lead out, lead forth, to raise up; to erect." University of British Columbia. Latin Dictionary. http://www.math.ubc.ca/~cass/frivs/latin/latin-dict-full.html#E

55 Rotblat, Joseph. ”Science and Human Values.” World Conference on Science in Budapest. 10 June 1999. 2. http://britishpugwash.org/wp/wp-content/uploads/2003/11/ScienceandHumanValues.pdf

41

Chapter 3: Testing Moral Principles

Chapter Summary: This chapter examines whether the proposed conception of moral

principles in combination with the notion of universal human responsibilities is a

defensible and viable model. Its viability is tested by assessing its criteria against moral

exemplars who embody strong evidence of moral understandings and responsibility, and

those who do not. A summary of the exemplars is presented at the end of the chapter.

Moral Exemplars

In proposing a set of basic moral principles, and having suggested a conception

of individual responsibility to attempt to provide a “backbone” for secular reason and a

universalised secular morality, merely suggesting principles and responsibility cannot

provide any type of test or evidence that the proposed conceptions are viable. Testing

the notions proposed is arguably best facilitated by examining individuals through their

experiences and actions as moral exemplars.

That is, examining the moral attitudes and positions of the exemplars helps

illustrate the moral principles and responsibilities advocated for in order to attempt to

make them more comprehensive and comprehensible. In this context, moral exemplars

are compared and contrasted with other individuals of approximately equal stature. For

both positive and negative exemplars, individuals were selected based on available

empirical evidence that is used to examine and support the claims made about their

42

moral orientations and actions. Resources will be examined, where available, such as

historical records, biographical information, autobiographies, videos, and selected

writings by the exemplars accordingly. Through examining the specific actions and

evidence of exemplars an attempt will be made to provide evidence for, or to gain

insights into the degree to which their morality is linked to their sense of individual

responsibility, and their actions can be seen to display the proposed model, or do not.

My interest in moral exemplars arose from attending a talk titled “How to Get Rid

of Nuclear Weapons” given by Joseph Rotblat at the University of British Columbia at the

Vancouver Institute Public Lectures series in March 1997.56 Learning of Dr. Rotblat’s

personal history as related to his involvement in the Atomic Bomb, and hearing his

intriguing talk on nuclear weapons all appealed to my long-standing personal interests in

peace and human conscience, and the failures of them.

Positive Exemplars

Positive moral exemplars are individuals who are seen to embody and display a

non-ordinary degree of moral principles, moral responsibility, and ethical action that is

deemed desirable as a more commonplace moral conception. Exemplars were chosen

as a sample of those who have been distinguished by being recognized through peace

or humanitarian awards, or forms of public consensus of exemplary conduct as reflected

in the context of the moral principles proposed in the Nietzsche/de Waal conception.

56 Rotblat, Joseph “How to get rid of Nuclear Weapons.” Vancouver Institute. University of British

Columbia. UBC Library Open Collections. March 1, 1997. Video recording. http://www.library.ubc.ca/archives/institute/vaninst9.html

43

Dr. Joseph Rotblat

Joseph Rotblat57 was a Nobel Peace Prize Laureate,58 and was awarded the

Nobel in 1995 for his work and contributions to the Pugwash Movement.59 He received

the prize in conjunction with the Pugwash organization that he was instrumental in

founding. The Pugwash movement arose out of Dr. Rotblat’s concerns with nuclear

weapons disarmament during World War II, in conjunction with the philosopher Bertrand

Russell. The “Pugwash Pact” 60 was the result of the Russell-Einstein Manifesto (1955).61

The Russell-Einstein Manifesto is a document and instrument confirmed and supported

by scientists and others at the time indicating the dangers of nuclear weapons and which

called for the peaceful settlement of international conflicts. Joseph Rotblat was among

the eleven original signatories.62 He was knighted in 1998.

During World War II Dr. Rotblat was involved in the building of the Atomic Bomb

in the “Manhattan Project” at Los Alamos New Mexico. When it became evident to him

and others that the Germans were no longer proceeding to build an atomic/nuclear

weapon, Dr. Rotblat asked to leave the Manhattan Project on the grounds of conscience.

In his autobiographical account “Leaving the Bomb Project” 63 Dr. Rotblat discussed his

57

Encyclopaedia Britannica. Sir Joseph Rotblat: British physicist and philanthropist. Biography. Updated 1/13/2016. Chicago. http://www.britannica.com/biography/Joseph-Rotblat/

58 Rotblat, Joseph. “Facts.” Peace Prize Laureates: Nobel Peace Prize Laureate 1995. Sweden: Nobel Media AB. 2016 http://www.nobelprize.org/nobel_prizes/peace/laureates/1995/rotblat-facts.html

59 Encyclopaedia Britannica, Ibíd.

60 Pugwash Conferences on Science and World Affairs. http://pugwash.org/

61 Ibíd., “Manifesto.” http://pugwash.org/1955/07/09/statement-manifesto/

62 Ibid.

63 Rotblat, Joseph, Dr. "Leaving the Bomb Project". Bulletin of Atomic Scientists, August 1985. 18.

44

reasons for leaving the project writing:

Sometimes Bohr stayed on and talked to me about the social and political

implications of the discovery of nuclear energy and of his worry about the

dire consequences of a nuclear arms race between East and West which

he foresaw.

All this, and the growing evidence that the war in Europe would be over

before the bomb project was completed, made my participation in it

pointless. If it took the Americans such a long time, then my fear of the

Germans being first was groundless. When it became evident, toward the

end of 1944, that the Germans had abandoned their bomb project, the

whole purpose of my being in Los Alamos ceased to be, and I asked for

permission to leave and return to Britain. Why did other scientists not

make the same decision? Obviously, one would not expect General

Groves to wind up the project as soon as Germany was defeated, but

there were many scientists for whom the German factor was the main

motivation. Why did they not quit when this factor ceased to be?

Several points pertaining to Dr. Rotblat’s decision and actions merit mention. First, Dr.

Rotblat was the only scientist to leave the Manhattan project on the grounds of

conscience. Second, the building of the bomb was a “legal” undertaking, sanctioned by

the governments of the U.S. and Britain. Third, the building of the bomb had been

deemed morally defensible, a necessity in fact at the time it was undertaken. Lastly, had

the bomb not been built when it was believed the enemy was building one of their own it

would have been morally indefensible not to, leaving the western powers and European

populations vulnerable to attack if the Nazis had succeeded in building their own.

Joseph Rotblat did not claim to be a pacifist or idealist: he had an acute sense of

the need for defence against aggression and an understanding of the necessity and duty

45

to preserve one’s own life and the lives of others, and hence the duty not to be complicit

in the violence of passivity. When the threat of the Nazis developing an atomic bomb

had ended, Dr. Rotblat recognized that all necessity for nuclear weapons development

with their inherent destructive capabilities to all life and the environment should end. It

was because of his moral convictions that he made his remarkable decision. He wrote:

The groups I have just described - scientists with a social conscience -

were a minority in the scientific community. The majority were not

bothered by moral scruples; they were quite content to leave it to others

to decide how their work would be used. Much the same situation exists

now in many countries in relation to work on military projects. But it is the

morality issue at a time of war that perplexes and worries me most.64

Here Dr. Rotblat acted on moral principles identical to those articulated in the

Nietzsche/de Wall conception of a higher order moral principle, and he demonstrated the

responsibility of addressing the problems of morality in war, and that could lead to war in

the first instance. In the case of the Atomic Bomb, had all the actors/agents involved

deliberated and been self-reflectively and responsibly moral in the way Dr. Rotblat was,

the bomb would not have been built, and not used, and hence no resulting dire threat of

nuclear arms would have resulted.

The decision to end his participation in the bomb project came at a cost to Dr.

Rotblat; he wrote that it altered his life and his scientific career. He subsequently spent

the remainder of his life working with Pugwash in efforts to reverse the course of what he

had participated in creating that was a threat to all life. It was in 1985 when he reflected

64

Ibid., 18.

46

on his actions in “Leaving the Bomb Project” stating:

After 40 years one question keeps nagging me: have we learned enough

not to repeat the mistakes we made then? I am not sure even about

myself. Not being an absolute pacifist, I cannot guarantee that I would not

behave in the same way, should a similar situation arise. Our concepts of

morality seem to get thrown overboard once military action starts. It is,

therefore, most important not to allow such a situation to develop. Our

prime effort must concentrate on the prevention of nuclear war, because

in such a war not only morality but the whole fabric of civilization would

disappear.65

Dr. Rotblat’s fears were well informed and well founded; indeed, his words strengthen

the case for advancing a conception of morality that focuses on being life supporting, so

that war and all forms of destructive behaviours are avoided. The threat of nuclear

weapons remains a grave danger today, perhaps more than ever with people who hold

fundamentalist beliefs having access to such weapons. His misgivings compel the

finding of a morality that would not permit people to be in conflicts that could lead to war.

Joseph Rotblat displayed a non-ordinary degree of moral awareness and

personal responsibility. He did so entirely through an internal locus of morality, which

research shows religion was no part. Joseph Rotblat was born and raised in a Jewish

family, but he did not follow the teachings or the imperatives of any religion or religious

moral code. While it may be the case that his upbringing had an influence on his sense

of morality, he did not make any claim to this effect and there is no evidence that can be

located in any of his autobiographical or other writings that he attributed his moral

65

Ibid., 19.

47

position or convictions to his upbringing. His only reflection on his early life is that his life

was happy. The lack of religious faith or motives external to Dr. Rotblat’s own self-

reflective and self-responsible sense of morality are notable by their absence in his

autobiographical accounts of his actions. This is true not only of his actions evidenced in

the paper “Leaving the Bomb Project,” but also of his other writings and biographical

information.

In a 1986 documentary film about his life titled “The Strangest Dream” his niece

recounts a conversation she had with him in which she asked if he was an atheist. He

replied “Not an atheist but an agnostic.” To which she asked “But why? I call myself an

atheist.” And he replied, “As a scientist I can never say that something is impossible.” 66

Further evidence that religion did not appear to influence Rotblat’s views is found

in an exchange with Dr. Daisaku Ikeda in the book A Quest for Global Peace: Rotblat

and Ikeda on War, Ethics, and the Nuclear Threat 67 where he states:

When I say I am an optimist, I do not simply believe that world conditions

will improve of their own accord. Nothing will change unless we make an

effort to make the world a better place. Each person must do whatever he

or she can to contribute something to this effort . . . Optimism is the ethic

I live by. It is not a religious sentiment, but it may be similar to your

religious views. Dr. Ikeda, we start off from different points, but we arrive

at the same conclusions.

66

Bednarsky, Eric. The Strangest Dream. National Film Board of Canada. 2008. https://www.nfb.ca/film/strangest_dream/ Chapter 21. Time 1:20:35

67 Rotblat, Joseph. & Ikeda, Daisaku. A Quest for Global Peace: Rotblat and Ikeda on War, Ethics, and the Nuclear Threat. (London: I. B. Tauris, c2007) 104.

48

Here, it is clearly evident that Dr. Rotblat both understood and advocated the notion of

individual responsibility for moral thought and ethical action. This is not a naïve view; it is

an observation that indifference or passivity will not suffice to improve the moral standing

of humanity, and it is an expression of an intention to anticipate effecting change for the

future. Nor is his a view that reflects the mistaken utilitarian philosophy of Jeremy

Bentham who advocated a moral view that people should advance the “Greatest good

for the greatest number” which necessarily implies questionable implications for the

unfortunate few. 68 Joseph Rotblat’s optimism suggests that all people should actively

work toward the greatest good for all: precisely what the moral conception from

Nietzsche and de Wall anticipates. His optimism is an ethical intention of responsibility.

Claims have been made that some individuals who were self-professed atheists

or agnostics, or antitheists recanted their position at or near the end of their lives and

claimed to have accepted God, or Jesus Christ, or any religion. Capitulation of long held

atheistic or agnostic (or other non-theocentric) positions may bring the moral behaviour

and moral convictions of some individuals into serious doubt. Claims could be made that

such people always had an underlying theistic belief or motive for their moral position

and that their moral stance had not been an authentically self-reflective and personally

responsible one. For example, such claims were made about the philosopher Antony

Flew, a lifelong atheist who was said to have abandoned his avowed atheism to become

a deist as he neared the end of his life.69 This claim was used to attempt to discredit

68

Crimmins, James E., "Jeremy Bentham", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2015 Edition), Edward N. Zalta ed. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2015/entries/bentham/

69 Grimes, William. “Obituary: Antony Flew, Philosopher and Ex-Atheist, Dies at 87.” New York: The New York Times Company. Published April 16, 2010. http://www.nytimes.com/2010/04/17/arts/17flew.html?_r=0/ Web.

49

some of his life’s work, or to claim his life and work were related to God.70

Controversial claims like these that have been levelled against Antony Flew are

problematic when the individual in question cannot be queried personally, and the claims

about them hence cannot be fully credited or disputed. However, they can cast a

plausible doubt on the moral position and motives of individuals. Claims of this type

might bring into question whether people such as Joseph Rotblat would truly have

represented a non-ordinary and self-responsible morality of the kind advocated for here.

Claims that he reverted to any type theocentric belief system or metaphysical worldviews

that informed his moral conceptions cannot be made about Joseph Rotblat, who died on

August 31, 2005 at the age of 96.71 Any claim to this effect can be disabused based on

first-person accounts from people who knew him personally.

At a symposium hosted at Simon Fraser University in 2014 titled “Peace and the

Environment: A Symposium Exploring the Legacy and Insights of Six Nobel Peace Prize

Laureates” I had the opportunity to meet Professor John Finney, a participant at the

symposium who presented on Joseph Rotblat. Prof. Finney was a colleague of Joseph

Rotblat in the Pugwash Conferences on Science and World Affairs organization and is

an Executive Committee member as trustee of British Pugwash Trust.72 He was also a

personal friend of Dr. Rotblat until the time of Rotblat’s death. I inquired of Professor

Finney whether he knew if Dr. Rotblat recanted his agnostic position, or made any

70 Strobel, Lee. Antony Flew on God and Atheism. Video Interview. California: San Bruno.

Youtube Inc. Feb 11, 2013. https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=VHUtMEru4pQ/ 71

Jones. G.O. “Joseph Rotblat Obituary.” Aug 31, 2005. The Guardian News. Sept. 2, 2005. Guardian News and Media Limited. 2016. http://www.theguardian.com/science/2005/sep/02/obituaries.obituaries

72 British Pugwash Trust. http://britishpugwash.org/what-is-pugwash/british-pugwash-trust/

50

reference or claim to have taken any personal view, or attributed any of his actions or

life’s work to the existence of God or religion as a source of his ethical actions, either at

the time he quit the bomb project, or at any time later in his life. Professor Finney stated

that “I got the impression that he was neutral to religion and that it did not play a

significant part in defining his ethical stance.” 73

In later correspondence Professor Finney also informed me that he asked my

question of Professor Robert Hinde (Executive Committee member of British Pugwash)

who worked closely with Joseph Rotblat and coauthored a book with him.74 Professor

Hinde replied to Professor Finney that he "could not remember him ever raising religion

in a significant way." Professor Finney also graciously shared a contact for Professor

Christopher (Kit) Hill, who authored a book75 about Joseph Rotblat and was a close

personal friend, and who knew him from 1960 up until the time of his death. Professor

Hill responded stating that “I never got a hint that his decisions and way of life were

specifically tied in to a particular formal religion."

Further confirmation came from Dr. Tom Milne (Trustee, British Pugwash Trust)

who worked as Joseph Rotblat’s personal assistant in the 1990’s and early 2000’s. Dr.

Milne worked closely with him and was a personal friend. Dr. Milne has shared that “as

far as I know he did not hold any religious beliefs, either at the time of the Manhattan

project or later in life.” There is also confirmation from Sally Milne (Executive Committee,

PeaceJam, British Pugwash). Sally is Tom Milne’s mother and who took over as

73

Personal email correspondence(s). Feb/Mar. 2014. Cited with permission June 2016. 74 Hinde, Robert A, and Rotblat, Joseph. War No More: Eliminating Conflict in the Nuclear Age.

(London and Sterling, Va.: Pluto Press. 2003) 75

Hill, Kit. Professor Pugwash: The Man Who Fought Nukes. (U.K.: Ryelands Publishing. 2008)

51

Professor Rotblat’s personal assistant at Pugwash when Tom left after completing his

PhD to work in education. Sally Milne remained Joseph Rotblat’s assistant and his close

personal friend up to the time of his death. Mrs. Milne affirmed that Joseph Rotblat

described himself as an agnostic and a humanist up to the end of his life. She added

that “his morality was always a very personal one, not based on any religion or particular

teaching, but based on trying to do good in the world and make it a better place.”

Considering the autobiographical information that Joseph Rotblat gave about

himself in the movie “The Strangest Dream,” along with his personal history and writings,

and combined with the consensus of the many people who knew him professionally and

personally, it is evident that his non-ordinary moral stance can be aligned with the

conception of self-reflective moral principles in the Nietzsche/de Waal concept, and his

actions were compelled by his sense of personal responsibility as reflected in the

Declaration of Human Responsibilities. His lifelong engagement with nuclear

disarmament and the eradication of nuclear weapons shows that his moral stance and

reasoning were, and remain unimpeachable.

From the magnitude and far-reaching implications of his actions throughout his

life for all humanity, it can be argued that Joseph Rotblat possessed a level of moral

maturity and integrity that is exemplary. While his example is perhaps anomalous, it

shows that a normative secular morality can exist and is attainable. Sally Milne summed

up his moral stance and life philosophy succinctly when she wrote of Joseph Rotblat that

“One of his dearest quotes when faced with difficulties was, “Remember your humanity

and forget the rest.” Joseph Rotblat stands as a pre-eminent moral exemplar. I will now

continue my “case studies” of exemplars with Fridtjof Nansen.

52

Fridtjof Nansen

Fridtjof Nansen is distinguished as a positive moral exemplar having received the

Nobel Peace Prize in 1922.76 Nansen was a Polar Explorer,77 adventurer, and a

humanitarian with many remarkable achievements to his credit. He was awarded the

Nobel Prize for

. . . his work in the repatriation of prisoners of war, his work for the

Russian refugees, his work in aiding the millions in Russia struggling

against famine, and now his work for the refugees in Asia Minor and

Thrace. Although this activity has been in progress for only a few years,

its extent and significance are such that the Nobel Committee has felt it

worthy of the great distinction of the Nobel Peace Prize.78

The Nobel Committee credited Nansen for five great humanitarian efforts that he

undertook at the behest of the International Red Cross, the League of Nations, the

Government of Greece, and the United Nations.79 Information in his biography states

that “[h]is father, a prosperous lawyer, was a religious man with a clear conception of

personal duty and moral principle. . .” 80 He was influenced by his father’s worldview, but

did not share his father’s religious beliefs. Nansen affirmed his father’s influence when

76

Nansen, Fridtjof. “Biography.” Peace Prize Laureates. Nobel Peace Prize Laureate 1922. Sweden: Nobel Media AB 2016 http://www.nobelprize.org/nobel_prizes/peace/laureates/1922/nansen-bio.html

77 Greve, Marit. Fridtjof Nansen. Margaret Ellson Davies., trans. Oslo: Aschehoug.1994. Cited in Nansen, Fridtjof. Polar Explorers. Fram Museum, Oslo, Norway. http://www.frammuseum.no/Polar-Heroes/Main-Heroes/Fridtjof-Nansen.aspx/

78 Nansen, Fridtjof. “Press Release.” Peace Prize Laureates. Nobel Peace Prize Laureate 1922. Sweden: Nobel Media AB 2016 http://www.nobelprize.org/nobel_prizes/peace/laureates/1922/press.html/

79 Nansen, “Biography.” Ibid.

80 Ibid.

53

he said: “By nature I am weak, what character I have stems from my strict upbringing.” 81

In researching Nansen to discover his motives, I found no documented evidence

that his motives or actions were for any reason other than to succour the suffering of

humanity; in particular of humanly caused suffering as the result of wars, displacements,

and famines related to war. He had no religious motives of his own: Nansen was a self-

declared lifelong agnostic who eschewed theocentric worldviews. He quoted Ralph

Waldo Emerson82 in a speech titled “Science and the purpose of life,” in which he said,

“. . . the religion of one age is, as a rule, the literary entertainment of the next. . . ” 83

Nansen also eschewed commonly held notions typified in theocentric world views:

In his younger years he dismissed the metaphysical concept of the soul.

Almost as a point of defiance he had, through his choice of theme for this

doctorate when a student of zoology, studied the central nervous system

of lower animals. He wanted to see whether there was any place where a

“soul” could exist . . . [Later] he thought that man had both intellect and

intelligence and that man had spirit. . . . [he] drew attention to this

presence of spirit and conscience as one of the most powerful forces in

the human condition.” . . . Fridtjof Nansen was an agnostic.84

Organizations and governments often called upon him to assist with difficult

problems as a man capable of doing the most challenging of humanitarian work ably and

81

Christophersen, Chr. A. R. “Fridtjof Nansen (1861-1930) A Life in the Service of Science and Humanity.” Nansen Dialogue Network. Norway: Lillehammer. 2015.http://www.nansen-dialogue.net/index.php/en/who-are-we/who-is-fridtjof-nansen/

82 Emerson, Ralph Waldo. The Spiritual Emerson: Essential Writings. Robinson, David M. ed. Boston: Beacon Press. 2004) 250.

83 Nansen, Fridtjof. “Science and the Purpose of Life." Speech published by the Rationalist Press Association, 1909, cited in A Biographical Dictionary of Modern Rationalists. https://ffrf.org/news/day/dayitems/item/14590-fridtjof-nansen.

84 Greve, Fridtjof Nansen. Ibid.

54

successfully. Nansen was an academic, scientist, explorer and adventurer. It is arguably

the case that humanitarian endeavours commandeered his time, of which he gave

abundantly and for no apparent reasons other than to succour human need and

suffering. His empathy and compassion were borne in his actions. His moral intelligence

appears to have had no reserve. Nansen was a positive moral exemplar who embodied

and reflected the moral principles and individual responsibility aligned with the

conception advanced here. Another case study is Wangari Maathai.

Wangari Maathai

Wangari Muta Maathai is the 2004 Nobel Peace Prize Laureate85 “for her

contribution to sustainable development, democracy and peace.” 86 and for her

humanitarian work. She is distinguished as the first woman to receive the Nobel Peace

Prize. Maathai started a grass-roots movement to counter deforestation in her native

country of Kenya through encouraging women to plant trees in what came to be called

the “Green Belt Movement” (GBM), for which she was awarded the Nobel Prize. Her

GBM initiative spread to numerous African countries, and it is estimated that

approximately twenty million trees have been planted on farms, school, and church

lands by women.87

Maathai’s work encompasses and encourages democracy, human rights (for

85

Maathai, Wangari “Facts." Peace Prize Laureates. Nobel Peace Prize Laureate 2004. Nobel Media AB 2014. 12 Jan 2016. http://www.nobelprize.org/nobel_prizes/peace/laureates/2004/maathai-facts.html

86 Ibid.

87 Maathai, Wangari. “Biographical." Peace Prize Laureates. Nobel Peace Prize Laureate 2004. Nobel Media AB 2014. 12 Jan 2016. http://www.nobelprize.org/nobel_prizes/peace/laureates/2004/maathai-bio.html

55

women in particular but for all people generally), and environmental conservation.

Responding to what she viewed as a depletion of the resources of earth that carried

devastating consequences, of which people are part, the right moral action in her view

was to capitalize on and spend her accomplishments and lifetime in the restoration of a

more life-sustaining and natural balance between humans and the environment. Maathai

acted in a way that is and was life supporting, species supporting, and reflected the

moral dimensions as described by Nietzsche/de Waal which anticipates the needs of not

only of humans, but of all species in a way that recognizes the essential dependencies

and mutuality necessary to life.

Maathai’s views and actions are not esoteric. They are pragmatic in that they are

properly understood to assert the essential connection to nature underlying and

supporting all life. The interconnectedness of moral and ethical values in relation to

nature as a means of survival and furthering life was the source of her actions. Maathai

is clear about her understanding of these concerns and the importance of them when

she states:

I came to realize that the work of the GBM was driven by certain

intangible values. These values were: love for the environment; a

gratitude and respect for Earth's resources; a capacity to empower and

better oneself; and a spirit of service and volunteerism. Together, these

values encapsulate the intangible, subtle, nonmaterialistic aspects of the

GBM (Green Belt Movement) as an organization. They enabled us to

continue working, even through the difficult times. Of course, I'm aware

that such values are not unique to the Green Belt Movement. They are

universal; they can't be touched or seen. We cannot place a monetary

value on them: in effect, they are priceless. These values are not

contained within certain religious traditions. Neither does one have to

56

profess a faith in a divine being to live by them. However, they do seem to

be part of the our human nature and I'm convinced that we are better

people because we hold them, and that humankind is better off with them

than without them. Where these values are ignored, they are replaced by

vices such as selfishness, corruption, greed, and exploitation.88

In attempting to apply a term other than the word “moral” to Maathai’s sentiments and

pragmatic aims, the word “wholesome” is apt, where the word has the meaning:

“promoting or indicating physical, mental, or moral health.” 89 Maathai did not derive her

morality from God or any theocentric views. She appears to have responded to the

vicissitudes of life on a deeper and more fundamental level connected to the earth and

to life, much as Joseph Rotblat and Fridtjof Nansen did, and from an internal locus. Her

motives are clear when she reflected that she had undertaken her actions based on an

inner drive, without making any attributions when she asserted: “However, I never

differentiated between activities that might be called ‘spiritual’ and those that might be

termed ‘secular.’” 90

Here Maathai demonstrates support for the principle that true morality in all

cases must seek the greatest good for all, and the greatest good that universalises to all

life and all that which we term nature - all species and the environment. She also

demonstrates the thoughtful and reflective sense of responsibility that was evident

through her actions, and particularly in her concern for nature and the desire to enable

life to flourish. In what may be seen and considered a holistic approach to secular

88

Maathai, Wangari. Replenishing The Earth: Spiritual Values For Healing Ourselves And The World. (Random House Inc., 2010) 13-14.

89 “Wholesome.” The Concise Oxford Dictionary. Ibid.

90 Maathai, Replenishing the Earth. Ibid.

57

morality and to life, Maathai’s actions and leadership affirm her as a positive moral

exemplar. She strongly displays the moral principles and sense of personal responsibility

found in a comprehensive conception of secular morality. Secular morality is also

exemplified through the experiences of philosopher Alphonso Lingis.

The Anonymous Exemplar

The philosopher Alphonso Lingis in The Community of Those Who Have Nothing

in Common relates a personal account of events that happened to him during his travels

in India, and of being taken into the care of a man who saved his life. His experience had

a profound effect on his views of morality and typical moral constructs that, in fact,

transcended his existing moral understanding as he recounts his story:

One night, sick for weeks in a hut in Mahabalipuram in the south of India,

I woke out of the fevered stupor of days to find that the paralysis that had

incapacitated my arms was working its way into my chest. I stumbled out

into the starless darkness of the heavy night. On the shore, gasping for

air, I felt he was naked, save for a threadbare loincloth, and all I could

understand was that he was from Nepal. How he had come here, to the

far south of the Indian subcontinent - farther by far than I who, equipped

with credit card, could come here from my home in a day by jet plane - I

had no way of learning from him.

He seemed to have nothing, sleeping on the sands, alone. He engaged in

a long conversation, unintelligible to me, with a fisherman awakened from

a hut at the edge of the jungle and finally loaded me in an outrigger canoe

to take me, I knew without understanding any of his words, through the

monsoon seas to the hospital in Madras sixty-five miles away. My fevered

eyes contemplated his silent and expressionless face, from time to time

illuminated by the distant flashes of lightning as he labored in the canoe,

58

and it was completely clear to me that should the storm become violent,

he would not hesitate to save me, at the risk of his own life.

We disembarked at a fishing port, where he put me first on a rickshaw

and then on a bus for Madras, and then he disappeared without a word

or glance at me. He surely had no address but the sands; I would never

see him again. I shall not cease seeing what it means to come to be

bound with a bond that can never be broken or forgotten, what it means

to become a brother. How indecent to speak of such things in the

anonymous irresponsibility of a writing he cannot read and a tongue he

cannot understand ! We know ourselves in our mortality.91

Lingis argues that there is a universal ”brotherhood” of man and humanity that is an

expression of a “natural” morality that exists in all people and is communicated and

experienced as a phenomenon independent of language, status, possessions, or beliefs

such as religions. It resides in our most fundamental existence and for Lingis, relates to

our common mortality or a “community of death” as he terms it.92 He notes that we all

face death eventually, and in recognition of this fact, he argues that we must all respect

our own life and the lives of others at the deepest level of existence so that we can make

the best of our lives while we may.

Thus, we are linked by our common humanity as a part of nature as the strongest

common bond to life – that we seek life before it is no more for us. Through recognition

of this deepest urge to live well, Lingis argues that we find a commonality of good that

can emerge when it is not inhibited. In this Lingis is arguably referring to a notion

91

Lingis, Alphonso. The Community of Those Who Have Nothing in Common. (Bloomington and Indianapolis. Indian University Press. 1994) 158 - 159.

92 Ibid., 159.

59

suggested by Jean-Jacques Rousseau that humankind is good by nature but is

corrupted by society.93 German psychiatrist Friedrich Perls refers to this “good” as

“actualization” by which he means that all living things will naturally grow to fulfill their

natural imperative to become moral beings provided their environment supports this, and

they are not interfered with in their development – “corrupted” if we accept Rousseau.94

The anonymous exemplar may either not be corrupted by society, or perhaps

had refused to be affected by any corrupting forces. It may also be the case that he had

no influences brought to bear on him at all, and that he was simply a man who was in

tune with nature, and understood intuitively that all living things deserve dignity and wish

to survive and to thrive. Alternately, he may have had religious convictions, or not, or

perhaps a tribal or indigenous spirituality. It is impossible to know with any certainty. It is

arguably true that the principles advocated in this work were operative in this man, and it

is certain that his sense of personal responsibility was operative insofar as it is indicated

by the extraordinary efforts he humbly undertook on behalf of Lingis.

No other inferences or attributions can be made about the anonymous man;

nothing is known of whether there was anything to compel him except empathy and

compassion for a person suffering and in need. This is evident in view of the fact he did

so at risk to himself during a storm, and with the additional responsibility of using the

presumably borrowed canoe of the fisherman. Notable, too, is the second anonymous

93 Rousseau, Jean-Jacques. The Social Contract and Discourses. trans. G.D.H. Cole. (London

and Toronto: J.M. Dent and Sons, 1923) 203. 94 Perls, Friedrich S., M.D., Ph.D. In and Out The Garbage Pail. (Lafayette, California: Real

People Press. 1969) No Page Numbers.

60

man who, according to Lingis, unhesitatingly and unselfishly lent his canoe, if it was his -

his lifeblood presumably - to the anonymous man to use to save Lingis’s life.95

While the locus of motives of these men cannot be known precisely, their actions

suggest that they were in accord with the moral principles advocated, of which Lingis

was recipient. The profound effect that being the beneficiary of morality of this kind had

on Lingis is evident in his description of the impression it left on him, to have had the

experience of his fundamental humanity recognized and to feel himself a “brother of

man.” Moreover, Lingis, through the acknowledgement he gave his benefactor when he

refers to the indecency of writing of a man he “knows cannot read or understand,”

displayed a profound sense of respect and responsibility for the acts of kindness

received. It is precisely this sort of mutual respect (reciprocity) and empathy for the life of

another that is articulated and affirmed by the moral principles in the Nietzsche/de Waal

and personal responsibility constellation. I will now turn to negative exemplars to

illustrate cases where morality is seen to have failed.

Negative Exemplars

Negative exemplars are individuals who have demonstrated lack of ideal types of

moral insight and understandings such as compassion, reciprocity, mercy, and a lack of

insights, awareness, motives, or courage in their ethical conduct. Exemplars are

examined to discover whether evidence of theocentric morality is present or absent, and

whether the moral principles and responsibilities can be shown to have been absent.

95

Lingis cannot make this clear as in his own words he did not know. From the context it seems more probable than not, but there is no certainty.

61

J. Robert Oppenheimer

J. Robert Oppenheimer was a theoretical Physicist born in the U.S. His parents

were of Jewish descent, but did not actively follow Judaism. Robert Oppenheimer did not

receive a Nobel Prize as the positive exemplars did; however, he received nominations

for a Nobel Prize for Physics three times; in 1945, 1951 and 1967.96 Oppenheimer was

the scientific director for the Manhattan Project overseeing the efforts of the vast

scientific community working at Los Alamos to build the Atomic Bomb.

On any account Oppenheimer was an intellectually brilliant man with reasoning

capabilities beyond those of most people, demonstrated by his list of accomplishments

working within science and in conjunction with research and teaching at Universities.97

Unlike Joseph Rotblat, Oppenheimer remained with the Manhattan project as did all the

other scientific staff once it was known that the Nazis had abandoned their efforts to

build an atomic weapon. He was at the same dinner party as Joseph Rotblat when a

conversation took place. Dr. Rotblat relates the occasion:

General Leslie Groves, when visiting Los Alamos, frequently came to the

Chadwicks for dinner and relaxed palaver. During one such conversation

Groves said that, of course, the real purpose in making the bomb was to

subdue the Soviets. (Whatever his exact words, his real meaning was

clear.)98

96 Cassidy, David. J. Robert Oppenheimer and the American Century. (New York: Pi Press. 2005) 178.

97 Ibid., 151-152.

98 Rotblat, “Leaving the Bomb Project.” Ibid., 18.

62

Oppenheimer would have been fully aware that the bomb was not needed to end

the war, and might have anticipated the consequences of continuing to supervise

building the bomb having scientifically based knowledge of its destructive potential, and

evidence from preliminary tests. Rotblat also relates that Niels Bohr, a senior scientist

and contemporary of Oppenheimer, was aware of and concerned with the continuation

of building the bomb and the multifaceted threats and its consequences. Dr. Rotblat

stated: “Sometimes Bohr stayed on and talked to me about the social and political

implications of the discovery of nuclear energy and of his worry about the dire

consequences of a nuclear arms race between East and West which he foresaw.” 99

It is impossible to credit that a man of Oppenheimer’s intellect and position of

responsibility, along with his close working relationship with Groves, did not understand

the implications and the critical nature of the problems that would result from completing

the bomb – and that he either suggested that the project end or be limited, rather than

share responsibility for actions that could not be redeemed. Oppenheimer did not

display evidence of any of the concerns and wisdom seen with Rotblat and Bohr.

Alternately, it might have been that he had objections but did not feel he was in a

position to make any assertions about the possibility of terminating the project, or leaving

his position at the project; however, there is no evidence that this was the case at that

time. He appears to have been single-minded in his desire to succeed with the bomb,

despite the changing motivations for building it. One possible reason he did not leave

might have been that he was aware of the agenda to subdue the Russians from the

outset. In this case, learning that the Nazis were not building one would have no bearing.

99

Rotblat, Ibid., 18.

63

Before joining the Manhattan project, Oppenheimer had religious leanings toward

Hinduism. He learned Sanskrit, read the Bhagavad Gita in that language, and claimed it

was what most shaped his philosophy in life.100 It is interesting that he had religious

leanings and followed the Hindu Holy Scriptures, given the position he was in, but that

his religiosity and the morality inherent in the Gita (Dharma) seem to have not influenced

his actions. With a full awareness and anticipation of the destructive power of the bomb

he had great responsibility in creating, he appears to suffer some sort of moral

confusion, or at least a foreboding of the wrong he was precipitating when he cited a

verse from the Bhagavad Gita two days before the test:

In battle, in the forest, at the precipice in the mountains, On the dark great

sea, in the midst of javelins and arrows, In sleep, in confusion, in the

depths of shame, The good deeds a man has done before defend him.101

Oppenheimer arguably appears to be attempting to pre-empt or assuage his conscience

and his own pending moral fall by defending himself on the basis that any good deeds

he had done before would balance or excuse what would follow. The day of the first test

of the Atomic bomb at the site named the “Trinity Site” he claimed to have thought of a

verse from the Bhagavad Gita (XI, 12): “If the radiance of a thousand suns were to burst

at once into the sky, that would be like the splendor of the mighty one. . . .” 102

100

Hijiya, James A "The Gita of Robert Oppenheimer" Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society. . (June 2000.) 144 (2). Archived from the original on May 15, 2013. Retrieved

December 16, 2013. https://amphilsoc.org/sites/default/files/proceedings/Hijiya.pdf 101

Hollinger, David A. "Afterward". In Carson, Cathryn; Hollinger, David A. Reappraising Oppenheimer: Centennial Studies and Reflections. (Berkeley, California: Office for History of Science and Technology, Univ. of California. 2005) 385–390.

102 Jungk, Robert. Brighter than a Thousand Suns: A Personal History of the Atomic Scientists. (New York: Harcourt Brace. 1958) 201.

64

From this evidence it appears there was a moral confusion by which he seemed

to be implying that he was of a mind that the terrible effects of the bomb were

splendorous and somehow related to a Godly divinity. Yet he had explicit knowledge of

the intention of the bomb which was designed to kill large populations of people in

Japan, and to exercise control over millions of others in Russia (i.e., Soviet Union) if

Groves was to be believed. It is difficult to know in retrospect with accuracy whether he

was justifying a terrible instrument of destruction as splendorous, or was elated in

enjoying the fruits of his labour in seeing the magnitude of the results, or both.

Oppenheimer’s sense of jubilance was noticed by physicist and Nobel winner

Isidor Rabi, who wrote "I'll never forget his walk; I'll never forget the way he stepped out

of the car . . . his walk was like High Noon . . . this kind of strut. He had done it." 103 We

may not know what his true moral stance was, or how he perceived of himself as an

agent of such destructive power once he had witnessed it. Following the tests of the

bomb, there was an abundance of evidence about its terrible destructive capacity.

When Groves had stated that the political purpose of the bomb was to subdue

the Soviets, Oppenheimer would have been able to surmise that the bomb would have

to be used against populations in order to make apparent the threat that the U.S. wanted

to pose to the Soviets. That would require a demonstration of its destructive capacity

and killing potential. Therefore, Oppenheimer had to have known the bomb would be

used against a population to “prove” its power, and it was, with horrific consequences.

103

Monk, Ray. Robert Oppenheimer: A Life Inside the Center. (New York; Toronto: Doubleday. 2012) 456–457.

65

Years later, after much personal turmoil in his life, in 1965 he appeared on a

television broadcast and cited another verse from the Gita, in which he appears to be

deeply remorseful for his actions and part in creating the bomb:

We knew the world would not be the same. A few people laughed, a few

people cried. Most people were silent. I remembered the line from the

Hindu scripture, the Bhagavad Gita; Vishnu is trying to persuade the

Prince that he should do his duty and, to impress him, takes on his multi-

armed form and says, 'Now I am become Death, the destroyer of worlds.'

I suppose we all thought that, one way or another.’104

Despite what appears to be his later moral misgivings, there is evidence that

reason alone cannot reliably provide a strong moral grounding or guarantee moral

agency and ethical actions. While it may be the case that for many reasons he felt he

could not leave the bomb project, or he had to remain for political or other reasons that

may not be evident, there is evidence that Oppenheimer did not always think in any

strong moral terms or exercise his moral autonomy or responsibility. Joseph Rotblat, in

his essay “Leaving the Bomb Project” shows that Oppenheimer was prepared to commit

crimes against humanity of kinds that were not strictly related to the bomb project, or

using the bomb. Instead, he proposed something sinister of his own design. Rotblat

wrote:

Recently I came across a document released under the Freedom of

Information Act. It is a letter, dated May 25, 1943, from Robert

Oppenheimer to Enrico Fermi, on the military use of radioactive materials,

specifically, the poisoning of food with radioactive strontium. The Smyth

104

Oppenheimer, Robert J. "Now I am become death.” Television Broadcast. 1965. The Decision to Drop the Bomb. National Science Digital Library. 2015. San Diego: AJ Software & Multimedia. http://www.atomicarchive.com/Movies/Movie8.shtml/

66

Report mentions such use as a possible German threat, but

Oppenheimer apparently thought the idea worthy of consideration, and

asked Fermi whether he could produce the strontium without letting too

many people into the secret.

He went on: "I think we should not attempt a plan unless we can poison

food sufficient to kill a half a million men." I am sure that in peacetime

these same scientists would have viewed such a plan as barbaric; they

would not have contemplated it even for a moment. Yet during the war it

was considered quite seriously and, I presume, abandoned only because

it was technically infeasible. 105

This letter compels a question whether Oppenheimer had considered the long-term

consequences of using radioactive weapons of this sort, or what the implications would

be to people and to the environment at large. The crucial question is how such moral

shortcomings could exist in man as intellectually gifted as Oppenheimer was.

Robert Oppenheimer is seen to have been morally confused and morally dis-

responsible; he appears to have intentionally ignored morality evidenced through his

own actions and words, yet he appears variously to have had deep misgivings about the

morality of his actions and what was being done, and his direct responsibility for it, while

in contrast citing his religious allegiance in what appears to be a glorification of the bomb

in likening it to divinity. The morality he interpreted or derived - or perhaps misinterpreted

- from the Bhagavad Gita contravenes the moral principles that hold that morality should

be life-supporting, life preserving, and life enhancing. With the war emergency no longer

imminent, Oppenheimer could have made the same choice as Rotblat, but he did not.

105

Rotblat, “Leaving the Bomb Project.” Ibid., 18.

67

Oppenheimer’s actions associated with the building of the bomb aside, which are

deeply problematic, and his willingness to abandon his humanity to seek ways of killing

people by radioactive poisoning and only abandoning the plan due to its infeasibility, are

clearly immoral and perhaps amoral in the context of the moral principles defined in this

work. There is no evidence of motives that relate to Nietzsche’s cornerstone of morality,

and he showed no empathy or compassion except in a retrospect. Robert

Oppenheimer’s words and his citing of the Bhagavad Gita at critical times suggest that

he had some level of consciousness of a moral awareness, though neither his religious

beliefs nor his personal responsibility compelled him to make different choices. I now

turn to another case study of a negative moral exemplar, Richard Feynman.

Richard Feynman

Richard P. Feynman was an American theoretical physicist and Nobel Prize

Laureate in Physics in 1965.106 His parents were non-religious and non-practising

Ashkenazi Jewish people from Russia and Poland107 and he declared himself an atheist

from an early age.108 Feynman was widely regarded as a genius, with an extensive

number of achievements and accolades in science and teaching to his credit including

the Albert Einstein Award (1954, Princeton); the Einstein Award (Albert Einstein Award

106

Feynman, Richard. “Facts.” Peace Prize Laureates. Nobel Peace Prize. 1965. Nobel Media AB. 2016. http://www.nobelprize.org/nobel_prizes/physics/laureates/1965/feynman-facts.html

107 Gleick, James. Genius: The Life and Science of Richard Feynman. (New York: Vintage. 1993) 25. cited in http://www.nobel-winners.com/Physics/richard_phillips_feynman.html

108 Feynman, Richard P., Ralph Leighton, ed. “What Do You Care What Other People Think?”: Further Adventures of a Curious Character. (W. W. Norton & Co. 1988) 25.

68

College of Medicine) and the Lawrence Award (1962).109 Feynman joined the Manhattan

Project in 1943 at the request of the U.S. government, and worked with other scientists

in building the bomb. Richard Feynman is a unique exemplar since in 1981 he described

his actions succinctly and transparently for his moral failings in a taped interview aired

on the British Broadcasting Corporation Television “Horizons” series.110

In the interview he confers his experience of his morality that related to his work

on the bomb, and his delayed reaction to the realization of the questions and concerns

of individual responsibility and morality after the bombs were dropped on Japan. In his

own words, he acted immorally and shirked any moral responsibility despite having an

acute awareness of the destructive capacity of the bomb and its portent for the future.

Feynman explicated his moral orientation most exactly and forcefully from his

assessment of his actions in retrospect:

There was also the problem, of course, of any moral thing involving

war. I wouldn't have much to do with that, but it kinda scared me

when I realized what the weapon would be, and that since it might be

possible, it must be possible. There was nothing that I knew that indicated

that if we could do it they couldn't do it, and therefore it was very

important to try to cooperate.

[In early 1943 Feynman joined Oppenheimer's team at Los Alamos.] With

regard to moral questions, I do have something I would like to say about

109

Feynman, Richard. “Biography.” Peace Prize Laureates. Nobel Peace Prize 1965. Nobel

Media AB 2016. http://www.nobelprize.org/nobel_prizes/physics/laureates/1965/feynman-bio.html/

110 Feynman, Richard. The Pleasure of Finding things out. The best short works of Richard P. Feynman. Video. British Broadcasting Corporation. Horizon Program. 1981 -1982 Min:16:00 to 20:48 http://www.bbc.co.uk/programmes/p018dvyg

69

it. The original reason to start the project, which was that the Germans

were a danger, started me off on a process of action which was to try to

develop this first system at Princeton and then at Los Alamos, to try to

make the bomb work. All kinds of attempts were made to redesign it to

make it a worse bomb and so on. It was a project on which we all worked

very, very hard, all co-operating together. And with any project like that

you continue to work trying to get success, having decided to do it. But

what I did - immorally I would say - was to not remember the reason that I

said I was doing it, so that when the reason changed, because Germany

was defeated, not the singlest thought came to my mind at all about that,

that that meant now that I have to reconsider why I am continuing to do

this. I simply didn't think, okay?

[On 6 August 1945 the atomic bomb was exploded over Hiroshima.] The

only reaction that I remember - perhaps I was blinded by my own reaction

- was a very considerable elation and excitement, and there were parties

and people got drunk and it would make a tremendously interesting

contrast, what was going on in Los Alamos at the same time as what was

going on in Hiroshima. I was involved with this happy thing and also

drinking and drunk and playing drums sitting on the hood of - the bonnet

of - a Jeep and playing drums with excitement running all over Los

Alamos at the same time as people were dying and struggling in

Hiroshima.111

Here Feynman makes all the observations relevant to this analysis of moral principles

and personal responsibility. First, he stated that he wanted and took no responsibility for

any moral aspect of his part in the bomb or the war despite clearly recognizing the

exquisite danger of this particular weapon. He then states there was a further moral

problem – he notes this when he mentions that they wanted to make a “worse” (more

111

Feynman, Richard. The Pleasure of Finding things out. The best short works of Richard P. Feynman. Jeffrey Robins, ed. (Cambridge: Helix Books – Perseus Books. 1999) 9-11.

70

destructive) bomb. Then, he plainly stated that he acted immorally when they knew the

Germans were no longer building a bomb, and he did nothing to change his course of

action or moral direction claiming that despite this knowledge he “simply didn’t think.”

Lastly, Feynman seemed to come to a belated realization of the profound depth

of the immorality of his own behaviour where he stated he was elated, excited, drunk

and happy at the result of the effects and devastation of the bomb, until it dawned on

him the extent of the death and terrible suffering it had caused to civilian populations in

Hiroshima. His comment that it “was an interesting contrast” could be a lack of empathy,

or at least an un-empathetic way to state it. He continued in the interview to discuss his

strong reaction and depression in response to his part in creating the bomb, and the

terrible and persistent threat that it posed to humanity thereafter; the fact that the total

annihilation of life was possible with weapons such as these:

I had a very strong reaction after the war of a peculiar nature - it may be

from just the bomb itself and it may be for some other psychological

reasons, I'd just lost my wife or something, but I remember being in New

York with my mother in a restaurant, immediately after [Hiroshima], and

thinking about New York, and I knew how big the bomb in Hiroshima was,

how big an area it covered and so on, and I realized from where we were

- I don't know, 59th Street - that to drop one on 34th Street, it would

spread all the way out here and all these people would be killed and all

the things would be killed and there wasn't only one bomb available, but it

was easy to continue to make them, and therefore that things were sort of

doomed because already it appeared to me—very early, earlier than to

others who were more optimistic - that international relations and the way

people were behaving were no different than they had ever been before

and that it was just going to go on the same way as any other thing and I

was sure that it was going, therefore, to be used very soon. So I felt very

71

uncomfortable and thought, really believed, that it was silly: I would see

people building a bridge and I would say "they don't understand." I really

believed that it was senseless to make anything because it would all be

destroyed very soon anyway, but they didn't understand that and I had

this very strange view of any construction that I would see, I would always

think how foolish they are to try to make something. So I was really in a

kind of depressive condition.112

The question arises: How can an intellectual genius abdicate his moral

responsibility, or not be able to ”think” about the consequences of his actions despite the

evidence that he did in fact possess a moral center which he realized belatedly? A

related question would be to ask how it is that intellectual intelligence can be divorced

from moral intelligence in the way that I have indicated as a chief cause of the failure of

secular reason to become a source of morality. His candour is compelling, yet many

questions remain about how it was possible that he allowed himself to continue on a

path that was so perilous, which he recognized at the time when he stated he was

scared when he realized “what the weapon would be.” 113

Further, it is arguably true that he felt a deep compulsion to discuss his morality

and moral failings from the time he was involved with the bomb given the context of

being interviewed so many years later. Without being questioned by the interviewer, he

volunteered his entire story of his own free accord suggesting he had a deep and long

held remorse. His voluntary expurgation might arguably have been a kind of confession.

It is notable by its absence that he was not offering his discussion as a caution

112

Feynman, Ibid., 10-11. 113

Ibid., 9.

72

specifically to other people, or specifically to other scientists, or to politicians: he was

explicitly concerned with his own actions and reactions and culpability. If he possessed a

sound moral center, how is it that his moral center was ignored at the time he and all

humanity needed it most?

The greater wisdom and morality would have suggested that once the imminent

threat that was the cause for building a bomb had ceased, that the much greater threat

to humanity and all species should cease as well. Insofar as that Feynman has related

his moral failings, he has indicated that the moral principles and personal responsibility

which I have argued for in this work were absent at the time they were needed. A

question arises as to what might have occurred if more of the scientists had chosen as

Joseph Rotblat did, and acted ethically rather than being complicit in building the bomb.

An interesting postscript is that Feynman stated plainly that he “didn’t have much

patience with what’s called the humanities even though in the university there were

humanities that you had to take.”114 The question arises as to what moral influences

might have been brought to bear if he had studied history and ethics and other subjects

in the arts and humanities before committing himself to an irrevocable act of history and

a lifetime of regret for his part in building the bomb.115 I now turn to the study of a

political figure whose moral compass is problematic.

114

Feynman, Ibid., 3-4. 115

While beyond the scope of this work, the question as to what use or good are the humanities in Universities may reveal or conceal some compelling information about the human condition and the essential value of the humanities. What if Feynman had studied the humanities?

73

Robert McNamara

Robert McNamara was an American business executive who aspired to politics

and served as Secretary of Defence to the United States Government under Presidents

John F. Kennedy and Lyndon B. Johnson from 1961 to 1968. He was a follower of the

Presbyterian faith. During his tenure he was responsible for increasing the role of the

U.S. in the Vietnam War. He had served in the U.S. Army Air Forces from 1943 to 1946

during which time he attained the rank of Lieutenant Colonel. His main task was to do

statistical analysis of the efficiency of fighting the war with the use of chemical defoliants

Agent Orange and other “Rainbow” chemicals, bombs, and cannon.116 During his time as

Secretary of Defence, he was responsible for increasing the number of U.S. advisers

from 900 to 16,000, and troops to almost 535,000 by June 30, 1968 in Vietnam.117

Death totals of military personnel from the Vietnam war, which the US entered

on November 1, 1955, and ended on April 30, 1975, were 58,202 Americans including

those missing in action (MIA), 220,357 South Vietnamese, 851,000 North Vietnamese

and Vietcong, 4,407 Korean, 469 Australian and New Zealand (allies), 252 Thailand, and

it is estimated that Vietnamese civilian deaths were in the millions and continue to rise,

owing to the long term effects of the defoliants.118

The terrible legacy of chemical warfare and the use of a defoliant named “Agent

Orange” which contained a deadly toxin, affected U.S. military and civilian personnel,

116

Karnow, Stanley. Vietnam, a History. (New York: Penguin Books, 1997) 271. 117

Hanna, Peggy. Patriotism, Peace and Vietnam: A Memoir. (Ohio: Springfield. Left to Write. 2007) 113-115.

118 Ibid., 107.

74

Allied military and civilian personnel, and the native peoples of North and South

Vietnam. Agent Orange continues to affect populations and the environment 41 years

after the end of the Vietnam War: Its contaminant, dioxin - now regarded as one of the

most toxic chemicals known to man - remains in Vietnam’s ecosystem in the soil and the

food supply. Nearly 4.8 million Vietnamese people have been exposed, causing 400,000

deaths. The associated illnesses include cancers, birth defects, skin disorders,

autoimmune diseases, liver disorders, psychosocial effects, neurological defects and

gastrointestinal diseases. According to the Red Cross of Vietnam, up to one million

people are currently disabled or have health problems due to Agent Orange, 100,000 of

which are children.119 The United States National Academies of Science, Engineering,

and Medicine; the Institute of Medicine (IOM) continues to monitor and study the effects

of Agent Orange reporting in the most recent “Veterans and Agent Orange: Update

2010” 120 and recognizes the long term effects due to the use of such deadly chemicals.

In Errol Morris’s 2003 documentary The Fog of War: Eleven Lessons from the

Life of Robert S. McNamara, 121 McNamara explained that the moral problems which

arose from engaging in an “unwinnable war” were the result of grave errors of judgment:

Okay. Any military commander who is honest with himself, or with those

he's speaking to, will admit that he has made mistakes in the application

119

Center for Research on Globalization. “Vietnam’s Horrific Legacy: The Children of Agent Orange” Global Research News. May 26, 2015 http://www.globalresearch.ca/vietnams-horrific-legacy-the-children-of-agent-orange/5451862/

120 United States National Academies of Science, Engineering, and Medicine, The Institute of Medicine (IOM.) Report: Veterans and Agent Orange: Update 2010. September 29, 2011. Last Updated: 8/19/2015. http://iom.nationalacademies.org/reports/2011/veterans-and-agent-orange-update-2010.aspx/

121 Morris, Errol. The Fog of War: Eleven Lessons from the Life of Robert S. McNamara. Documentary. December 19, 2003 http://www.errolmorris.com/film/fow_transcript.html

75

of military power. He's killed people unnecessarily - his own troops or

other troops - through mistakes, through errors of judgment. A hundred,

or thousands, or tens of thousands, maybe even a hundred thousand.

But, he hasn't destroyed nations.122

McNamara also went on to state that he had been a statistical analyst working for

General Curtis LeMay of the U.S. Army Air Force, the arm of the military that firebombed

civilian populations in Japan and later the dropping of the Atomic Bomb during World

War II. In what seems an almost cold and confused recollection of events, he related a

conversation he had with Curtis LeMay:

We burned to death 100,000 Japanese civilians in Tokyo — men, women

and children, Mr. McNamara recalled; some 900,000 Japanese civilians

died in all. “LeMay said, ‘If we’d lost the war, we’d all have been

prosecuted as war criminals.” “And I think he’s right. He - and I’d say I -

were behaving as war criminals.” “What makes it immoral if you lose and

not immoral if you win?” he [McNamara] asked. He found the question

impossible to answer.123

Here several of McNamara’s moral confusions are noteworthy: one is that McNamara

did not seem interested or capable of undertaking a statistical analysis of the moral

dimensions of the war or his significant part in it prior to commencing his fateful acts. His

chief regret, by all accounts, is that he failed at winning an “unwinnable” war in Vietnam.

From his comments, it appears that he remained under the impression so many years

122

Ibid. 123

McNamara, Robert S. In Retrospect: The Tragedy and Lessons of Vietnam. New York: Vintage Books. 1996. Print. Cited in Morris, Errol. The Fog of War. Documentary. December 19, 2003/. Weiner, Tim. Robert S. McNamara, Architect of a Futile War, Dies at 93 Cited in New York Times Newspaper. The New York Times Company. July 6, 2009. http://www.nytimes.com/2009/07/07/us/07mcnamara.html?pagewanted=all&_r=0

76

later that the war would have been “not immoral” provided they had won.

While McNamara appears to have experienced guilt or regret in his public

contrition over losing the war, and for lives lost immediate to the war that he was greatly

responsible for, there seems to be little or no concern for the longer term effects of the

emotional impact from death and destruction to the spheres of family and loved ones of

all the people that were killed or injured and who were irrevocably impacted. Also at

issue is the concern of the effects to people in service in the U.S. Military and the

general population of the U.S. and its allies. This includes civilian populations of Vietnam

and the enemy, and it appears there was little regard, if any at all, for the fauna or the

environment of Vietnam. McNamara’s logic seems to be that had the U.S. won the war

that these losses, and the grief and destruction would have been statistically acceptable

or unworthy or notice or concern - and moral in his terms - or at least, not immoral.

Robert McNamara is iconic of the negative exemplars: In his asking the question

what makes it immoral if a war is lost, and not immoral if it is won, there is a unique

opportunity for an insight into what is responsible for the failure of morality: Two factors

are especially noteworthy: one is that McNamara’s moral conceptions do not include

what is explicitly moral; instead he is only concerned with what qualifies as immoral (to

lose) or “not” immoral (to win.) There is no evidence of personal responsibility for one’s

moral thoughts and decisions, except in the negative – what is immoral and why. The

question of what is properly “moral” or constitutes ethical action is neither considered nor

apparent in McNamara’s thinking. The second and arguably most critical of points is that

McNamara, based on his own language and statements, does not realize that winning or

losing war is not the proper criterion: he misses the fact that war itself is a crime against

77

life, and is itself immoral, and thus raises the question as to whether war can ever be

moral or ever truly necessary or just, or justifiable.

Whatever the stated purpose of war, it is aggression and violence, and in the

context of Nietzsche/de Waal/Einstein, abnegates the moral principles argued for in this

paper. In terms of morality there is no “Just war” there is only a “Just defense” according

to the dictates of nature, and the natural desire to “avoid pain and annihilation and to

survive and to thrive.” Here, a lack of awareness is plainly visible not only of the correct

moral dimensions of war for McNamara, but of his own failure to be able to reason

morally in a way that leads to the only life-supporting conclusions available or possible.

Any war is the complete failure of humanity to find or create solutions to the problems

that are the cause of wars. And with prodigious intellects like that of McNamara, the

question arises why and how such demonstrably powerful intellects fail to make these

connections, or have any awareness of the broader problems and moral concerns or

human suffering. Despite the moral confusion he experienced by his own admission and

from his own testimony, McNamara also clearly abrogated morality derived from his

professed Christian faith. He thus demonstrates a lack of fundamental moral principles

and of personal responsibility by taking refuge behind the impersonal in his appointed

role of Secretary of Defense during the war.

Summary Discussion of Exemplars

Examining the actions and the moral stance of positive exemplars shows there

are shared traits that are tested against the moral principles advanced from Nietzsche,

de Waal, and Einstein, and the ideal of self-reflective and self-responsible thought and

actions that are clearly operative. Each positive exemplar displays a high degree of

78

personal responsibility and the wisdom of a depth of concern for their own humanity, the

humanity of others, of other species, and the environment. None professed motives

from theocentric imperatives, and none displayed indications of failures of reason viewed

in the context of the moral principles, or at all.

In examining each of the positive exemplars, the principles and notion of

responsibility have been shown to be universal to them - indicating that what is proposed

does in fact work, and may be operative on a wider scale – making it both a viable and

defensible proposition. In the case of the anonymous exemplar that saved Lingis, the

individualistic and personal nature and scope of his actions indicates the profound effect

the moral actions of one person may have on the life of another. The greatness shown in

this example of the intimacy of a moral action between two people is as significant as the

greatness of the other positive exemplars, and indicates and supports the case for the

importance that all people can be individually responsible for their own morality.

Negative exemplars in contrast, by their own actions and declarations shown in

evidence did not demonstrate the moral principles or personal responsibility advocated

for in this work, and they evidently did not exercise the self-reflective choice of personal

ethical orientations or behaviours, which resulted in their immoral actions. Shared traits

of negative exemplars are the immoral intentions and actions they refused to recognise,

or the refusal of personal responsibility at times it was imperative to forestall immoral

actions. In all cases negative exemplars acted contrary to the moral principles by which

they were assessed and some acted contrary to their religious backgrounds or religious

beliefs, and the moral imperatives from those authorities.

79

In Robert Oppenheimer’s case, he appeared to be in conflict by a strong tension

of opposites between his moral center and his actions, and his religious/spiritual beliefs.

If he had no moral compass or moral center of his own, he may have been confused by

the conflicted dictates of his spiritual views, or his interpretations or misinterpretations of

them. However, the fact that he was arguably morally conflicted means, it seems, that

one pole of his psychological moral struggle was to act morally, which would have

required that he take responsibility for it, which he did not.

Richard Feynman articulated how his dispossession of responsibility for his

actions and his active thinking processes resulted in his later strong reaction to the

consequences and his moral abnegation of the nuclear weapon he had helped create. In

viewing the video interview and seeing his discomfiture, it is arguably true that not taking

responsibility for one’s moral and ethical actions had a very high cost for him, although

not as high as for the victims of the atomic bomb, or humanity at large.

For Robert McNamara, there is evidence of a professed disconnection among

the character traits that include his intellect and drive for success, an exclusion of his

religious grounding, his lack of moral intelligence showing difficulties with

comprehension of morality at a profound level that is beyond the scope of this work to

discuss.

This analysis is not intended as personal condemnation of any of the negative

exemplars in any sense. Rather, it is a condemnation of their actions or inactions, and of

the societies and cultures of belief that can arguably be seen to have contributed to the

compromise of their moral compasses, or prevented them in other ways from realizing

80

their full moral potentials. The intention is only to attempt to examine and support the

moral propositions advanced here as part of a critical process in order to investigate

whether the principles and responsibility were present or absent. Furthermore, they are

indices of the potential viability and usefulness of what is proposed if it may be

disseminated. Indeed, the loss of moral capacities is a heavy burden for all humanity.

Here, we seek to learn from historical errors and either to inform people of their morality,

or seek to use these tragic examples as a form of moral exhortation.

Discussion of Viability

The proposed model of morality/ethics is one that is demonstrated to anticipate

and facilitate the transition from metaphysical and authoritarian sources of morality, to

morality and ethical actions with an internal locus. The model can provide a missing

essence for secular reason if the tenets of the UDHR, and the Nietzsche/de Waal and

Einstein/ethical axiom constructs are observed and enacted as individual personal

responsibilities. The integrity of this secular conception of morality compels me to the

conclusion that it is both viable and defensible based on the demonstrated evidence of

all the principles and sense of personal responsibility found in the positive exemplars.

With the empirical evidence of the positive exemplars, it is shown to provide an

alternative means of establishing new normative moral values, complete with the

reasons and method to attain it provided people can be educated in the necessity of it.

Its strength will come from the intention intrinsic to it: that people may challenge

and destabilize current moral views that are argued to have failed, and see the

advantage in becoming more fully human and humane, and decent. It can arguably help

81

create a world where people’s best interests are known to be identical with those of all

humanity by learning that there is an alternative worldview that has the potential of

reducing conflict, and enhancing human relations independent of varying belief systems.

The conception of morality posited in this essay can be argued to be operative at a level

below that of individual or shared beliefs: It can be demonstrated to be effective through

reason and application, and requires no beliefs at all except knowledge of the necessity

to mature and become responsible. Here, necessity refers to the indispensability of the

natural imperative in the context of survival for people to become responsible in life. If all

means of psychological, ideological or material support were removed, many people

would not be able to stand on their own, independently, and survive and thrive. This is a

position of weakness, and dependency - not one of maturity and self-reliance.

The principles have the feature and advantage of being an integral conception

that does not require or admit of being dependent on moral commands from external

authority, but does not necessarily exclude moral knowledge from an external referent

such as a positive moral exemplar understood as a wise guide. This conception of

morality provides a self-test, combining rational and emotive criteria by which to

deliberate what is truly moral. It provides a method that confirms the outcomes of the

test, and encourages the intrinsic and internal self-referential locus of authority and

responsibility in order to effect the best moral judgments and actions.

Insofar as responsibility is operative from an internal locus of a personal moral

compass, it emphasizes responsibility over accountability, although both are important to

morality. Thus responsibility for moral or immoral acts cannot be externalized to any real

or imagined authority. It is intended to complement current moral codes to aid in the

82

transition and evolution toward secular morality, as well as retain whatever necessary

protections are derived from the existing codifications of theocentric or legalistic morality

while the transition occurs.

A further indication of the viability of this model is anticipated in the potential

longitudinal project of encouraging the moral and responsible growth and maturity of

individuals of all ages, effecting trans-generational change. Patricia Churchland, in her

work “The Neurobiological Platform for Moral Values” states: “How do we get from

familial caring to broader community-wide values such as honesty, loyalty, and courage?

The answer has two inter-twined parts: learning by the young, and problem solving by

everyone.” 124 Here, the suggestion is that people of any age or disposition may learn.

Interestingly, each of the negative exemplars displayed a tendency for delayed

moral awareness, or a kind of latent morality perhaps. This suggests the possibility that

people do have innate tendencies for morality, which either remain undeveloped,

occluded, or become corrupted (cf. Rousseau.) Further, there is an intuitive sense that

people who may have a “latent” moral compass or sense at any age may benefit from

being exposed to the moral model proposed in order to develop or reveal their moral

being. If this is arguably true, there is an indication that exposing individuals to training

and education of an essential understanding of the “processes” of morality understood

as insights and understanding, as differentiated from, and opposed to teaching it as a

“product” as rules/commands, may yield positive results. Educating people to this model

124 Churchland, P.S. “The Neurobiological Platform for Moral Values.” Behavior 151. (p.291)

(2014) 283 – 296. Cited in de Waal, Frans, ed. Evolved Morality: The Biology and Philosophy of Human Conscience. Leiden, NLD: BRILL, 2014.

83

at an early age may aid in a more integrated moral development preventing confusing

and corrupting influences from interfering with people’s natural tendency to be moral or

have “natural morality” during the formative years. It is arguably true that the best way

for the young to grow is by being in the company of, and through the examples of moral

exemplars.

However, in suggesting moral principles and individual responsibility as the

internal locus of morality I am seeking to imagine how to reverse a long historical pattern

and tendency for attachment to external loci of authority and the power of, and

submission to authority. As such, adult age or self-aware and self-responsible positive

exemplars for children are in short supply in mainstream populations to provide the

“environment” children need, as evidenced by the vast social/moral problems in the 21st

Century. Thus, it is arguably true that people of all ages must be learners, and the

general population needs to engage in ethical problem solving.

One criticism and limitation of the proposed model of secular morality is that

while this specific model is shown to be efficacious through examination of exceptional

positive exemplars, there are no empirical studies specifically relating to what is

proposed as a developmental or remedial model, and hence no data or longitudinal

effects have been collected or observed formally. With any soft evolution of human

consciousness, there is no expectation of rapid or revolutionary results. There has been

little change in moral codes and moral authority for approximately three millennia since

the emergence of the Old Testament Bible/Genesis in the Western world. Long held

methods and beliefs that provide homeostasis are often not relinquished, or change

accepted with facility, posing a further challenge.

84

Transitions of moral consciousness can reasonably be conjectured to take

decades or centuries to show significant change. Another concern could be the

resistance to the notion of personal responsibility for those who would have difficulty

(emotionally or practically) for taking responsibility and who would experience it perhaps

as an imposition or a burden. Further, there may be resistance imposed from institutional

concerns (e.g., theocracies that do not want to relinquish their notions or authority), and

the unwillingness of people to abandon their allegiance to such types of organization.

However, I believe that if the appeal is broad enough, this will abate.

The interest of this work has been to engage the “problems of morality” and the

question of a missing element in secular reason that responded to my concerns of

authoritarian forms of morality and their diminution, and the claims that secular reason

had failed in its expectations. In responding to this question and concerns, I have

brought together related kinds of information from various discourses, disciplines, and

agencies and amalgamated them to essay a notion of universalising secular morality. I

have also attempted to respond to the need, intangibly expressed, of humanity in

transition and to meet the needs of a rapidly and perhaps radically changing and

globalizing world, and the needs of people who are required to adapt to changing

consciousness.

The question and challenge for secular reason has been in what way to envision

a missing element, and how to understand what underlies the process of enabling

people to become independent moral agents that are self-aware, and have the capacity

to be self-reflective in order to attain moral maturity and ethical agency. Throughout this

work I have attempted to propose a workable conception of morality and an ethic that

85

seeks to provide a coherent and integral model of morality. In concluding, it may be

useful to reiterate the essence and elements of it here to bring the various aspects and

the intentions that compelled it together. In what may be termed a universal secular

morality, for lack of a better, it is as follows:

A universal secular morality binds reason to the dignity and intrinsic value of

people in an absolutist way that reflects the tenets of the UDHR. It is life supporting, life-

furthering, life-preserving, species-preserving, and perhaps species-rearing in a way that

is universally true for all people and never contingently true. Integral to it is that it

necessarily holds the two pillars of morality and our capacities for reciprocity-fairness

(Golden Rule) and empathy-compassion paramount as our inviolable emotional

referents. It stands in recognition of the ethical axiom that all humanity at its existential

core is fundamentally the same. It is realized in the knowledge that all people should

exercise their individual responsibility to affirm all these foundations, be self-reflective on

them, and deliberate their ethical actions as responsible moral agents.

Morality is a complex subject: no single treatment can provide a substantive

account of all aspects of what may constitute morality or all that is contingent upon it.

Having recognized that, it is arguably true that proposing a set of basic principles can

provide a referent in the quest for a post post-secular morality that reduces violence and

humanly caused suffering in the short term, and promotes human unity and peace in the

longer term.

To suggest that people accept the moral principles and responsibilities cannot

transfer morality from one type of authority to another. Instead, it is intended to merely

86

recognize a fundamental truth of nature: That we are all responsible for our own lives,

and our morality is essential to our ability to survive and to flourish, extending to

recognizing that the most efficacious way to live is benignly and in truth. The morality

proposed does not represent a system of rules; rather, it is a mode of consciousness

and way of thinking about oneself and others, and the world we all live in. To inform

people that they must be responsible is itself an act of responsibility in working to

provide people with life skills and knowledge that can enhance and preserve their lives

more efficaciously. In this sense it is arguably a human good that if all people would

observe and practice creates a better world for all in a way that is an expression of our

best capacities and the highest thrusts of life, tempered by intelligence and wisdom.

Through reflecting on the broad historical tendencies of humanity to better our

condition, a notion of rights aids in establishing both a foundation for secular reason, and

also provides a means to connecting the constellation together in what purports to be a

universal conception of morality for humanity that is secular, but can also be adopted by

religions of any kind. In binding fundamental human good to a secularized morality that

universalises, we may arguably operate on deeper psychological and emotional levels

that promote or allow people to flourish, which we desire. It remains to be seen.

Here, I am hoping that articulating fundamentals of an alternative conception of

morality will serve to provide a basis for examination and discussion, and the minutiae of

details and of ethics as the study of morality will follow on that. Moreover, I wish to

emphasize that the foundations of morality I have tried to present be understood and

shared as a process and part of life, as differentiated from a “project” of heroic

proportions. Rather, it is intended to relate to, and appeal to the dignity and decency of

87

people in a manner that resonates with them on many levels as knowledge that is

hopefully recognised as fundamentally “right” for all humanity. As well, it cannot go

unmentioned that people should also be unfailingly moral to themselves, as it is arguably

the case that many people unwittingly inflict pain and suffering on themselves. This

proposed conception of morality applies to all people. There can be no exceptions. No

people were born to exist to suffer, and should not.

In commending a conception of a universalising consensual secular morality and

a shift in moral paradigms, I would provide one final example and test of what is

proposed. If readers were to have their life judged for any reason, and were faced with

severe consequences or annihilation, and it appeared there was no absolution - which

conception of morality would they prefer to be judged by? Competing versions of

internally inconsistent theocentric morality? Or a legalistic morality that may have unjust

laws or could be instrumentalized by reason of a kind that may lack a full measure of

humanity? Or would readers prefer this secular and universalising conception anchored

to reason and the value and dignity of people found in human rights, to a life supporting

cornerstone of moral pillars, and an inarguable and irreducible ethical axiom combined

with individual responsibility that sees all people thinking and acting as moral and ethical

agents? For some this may be a difficult and challenging choice, for others, perhaps not.

Joseph Rotblat was fond of saying: “Remember your humanity and forget the rest.” 125

To this we can now add: “Remember everyone’s humanity and forget the rest.”

125

Milne, Sally. Personal correspondence. Ibid.

88

Epilogue

Transitions

Articulating a universalising theory of secular morality intended to address 21st

Century moral concerns with growing populations, increased migration, greater inter-

cultural and social exposure, technological developments, and changing global

consciousness requires that the universalising morality be brought to people’s

awareness. It must be disseminated in age and culturally sensitive and appropriate

ways, and tested for its value by the response to it as broadly as possible. My initial

intention would be to plant a “seed” of new knowledge and hope for its uptake. Here, the

intention is not to “advance” a conception of a universalising morality as an authoritative

program. Instead, the shift of the paradigm is intended to occur by putting it on offer, and

if people recognize for themselves any intrinsic value it may have, they may hence

accept and adopt it of their own accord. With this important caveat noted, it does require

that the information be presented for people to have knowledge of it. In a globalized and

networked world, there are many possible ways to present the information.

One initiative and method would be to publish the principles and Declaration of

Responsibilities (the “universal secular morality” in toto) on the Internet (World Wide

Web and social media venues) to offer the information, and provide a feedback

mechanism that could be accurately or usefully assessed (insofar as any study in “social

sciences” can be.) As a research and delivery platform the Internet provides a relatively

low cost outreach to make the information accessible around the world to individuals

89

who use this type of resource, and to get reactions, criticisms, or responses to it.

It could be published in a downloadable and redistributable form that introduces

the notion and explains its purpose in language that is accessible to all people, and then

to create and offer companion “instruction” guides that explicate how to access and

understand the material, and inform people how to implement it in understandable and

practical ways. Each principle and article of the declaration of responsibilities could be

examined and explained in plain language, with concrete examples as to how to

interpret, understand, and enact them.

Training and education would require two components: theoretical, and practical.

The theoretical would focus on the abstract elements and concepts of what is life, and

thence what is understood as life supporting, life enhancing, empathy, and compassion,

and so forth. The practical would seek to define useful examples to develop skills of

judgment of moral values and issues, life skills to assess conflict situations, negotiation

of moral deliberation, and synthesis of moral knowledge, etc., for a few examples. Here

it is important to note that this is intended as an experiential “learning-by-doing” model

that actively engages people in various learning models (e.g., moral literacy,

engagement/enactment exercises, and real-world experience.)

A second means to advancing and testing the proposal would be to design

educational materials and introduce them in educational settings: for example, secular

public schools, private elementary and senior secondary schools, colleges, universities,

and technical training institutes that have course content that might have moral

dimensions. Initial research efforts via public outreach or in educational institutions

90

would anticipate offering the information at the highest level of generality, and if interest

was seen to develop, it could become more detailed and specific according to audience

preferences and feedback, and demographic and financial considerations.

For any endeavour to compile empirical evidence there would be challenges in

assessing the qualitative results of audiences as measures of the appeal or success.

Quantitative results of numbers of participants, response surveys and opinion polls, their

ages and geo-locations etc., would be useful as measures of interest that would provide

data as to how best deliver the content according to the needs of varying populations. As

what purports to be a novel approach to understanding and teaching about morality, my

proposed research will provide information on best practices in content delivery

(pedagogy) in a range of classroom curriculum design, computer games, print or digital

media, educational software, social networking, and public forums or keynote speaking

to name a few. What is presented here is a tentative listing of possibilities, and I cannot

anticipate all the ways and means that people might be engaged by it, and with it.

Future Research and Interests

Beyond the completion of this work, I desire to continue engaging and creating

novel ideas and ways of investigating human concerns as these hold a great and

compelling appeal. My special interest in Peace remains a chief priority as that relates to

all other interests. Other endeavours would include continuing with advanced studies in

the humanities seeking to further develop new works that are in progress at the present,

pursuing research opportunities, or attempting to create new knowledge and original

works within the academic environment. Another possibility is to pursue other interests in

91

the humanities privately and perhaps to attempt to write books to market publicly that

have been on hold, and other projects such as productised information web sites.

I have several specific research and writing interests (that I have commenced)

that may admit of alternative approaches, methods, and understandings of human

consciousness. For example, one research interest is investigating and revealing ways

in which people from all parts of the world, and of differing beliefs and cultures can all

respond to abstract universal truths about their humanity, contingent on the type of

language that is used to convey them. This thesis assumes there is knowledge of a kind

that has the ability to bypass the cognitive structures and mental filters of mind, and

makes a direct appeal to deeper, central, and universal human capacities and knowing.

Initial informal investigations suggest an innate capacity for recognition of “universal”

forms of knowledge despite language barriers (with accurate translations), ideation,

levels of education, levels of intelligence, or other factors assumed to limit or restrict

access to fundamental human goods and knowledge.

I have a further interest in investigating the intriguing question “What is the

meaning of life”? A theory attendant to this question is that it is putatively the wrong

question in relation to what the question is intended to appeal to. A wrong question may

never result in a correct or satisfying answer, and it is possible that this has not been

investigated fruitfully. An alternative question and approach may provide the answer,

though obliquely, or from a different perspective and understanding.

Through investigating novel approaches to these enduring questions and

concerns, it may be possible to articulate a substantive justification for the arts and

92

humanities, which may serve to strengthen their presence in societies increasingly

focused on money, production, and technologies, but which eschew the spiritual and

emotional needs of humanity at large. It is arguably true that the arts and humanities

remain an important need for people with the exponential increases in populations,

diaspora and cultural diffusion, technological advances, and the uncertainties of the

future. We have to ask what the future might be like if we ignore the spiritual for the

material, and whether there is a price to bear for ignoring this important aspect of our

humanity. It is surely worth examining and essaying this type of knowledge, and there is

no desire to turn away from doing so. There is nothing more interesting than the human

mind and consciousness.

93

References

Aylesworth, Gary, "Postmodernism", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2015 Edition), Edward N. Zalta, ed. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2015/entries/postmodernism/ Web. (Accessed May 16, 2016)

Bednarsky, Eric. “The Strangest Dream” National Film Board of Canada. 2008. https://www.nfb.ca/film/strangest_dream. Chapter 21. Time 1:20:35. Web. (Accessed May 16, 2016)

Bender, Courtney. “Religion and Spirituality: History, Discourse, Measurement.” Social Science Research Council. Jan 24, 2007. http://religion.ssrc.org/reforum/Bender.pdf (Accessed June 16, 2016)

Breasted, James Henry. Ancient Time or a History of the Early World, Part 1. Whitefish, Montana: Kessinger Publishing. 2003. (p.141) Print.

British Pugwash Trust. http://britishpugwash.org/what-is-pugwash/british-pugwash-trust/ Web. (Accessed May 16, 2016)

Cambridge Dictionaries online. Moral Compass Cambridge University Press 2013. http://dictionary.cambridge.org/dictionary/british/moral-compass Web. (Accessed May 16, 2016)

Cassidy, David. J. Robert Oppenheimer and the American Century. New York: Pi Press. 2005. (p. 178) Print.

Centre for Research on Globalization. “Vietnam’s Horrific Legacy: The Children of Agent Orange” Global Research News. May 26, 2015 http://www.globalresearch.ca/vietnams-horrific-legacy-the-children-of-agent-orange/5451862/ Web. (Accessed May 16, 2016)

Christophersen, Chr. A. R. Fridtjof Nansen (1861-1930) A Life in the Service of Science and Humanity. Nansen Dialogue Network. Norway: Lillehammer. 2015. http://www.nansen-dialogue.net/index.php/en/who-are-we/who-is-fridtjof-nansen/ Web. (Accessed May 16, 2016)

94

Churchland, P.S. “The Neurobiological Platform for Moral Values.” Behavior 151. (p.291) (2014) cited in de Waal, Frans, ed. Evolved Morality: The Biology and Philosophy of Human Conscience. Leiden, NLD: BRILL, 2014. (p.283 – 296) ProQuest ebrary. 16 May 2016. http://site.ebrary.com.proxy.lib.sfu.ca/lib/sfu/detail.action?docID=10846294 Web. (Accessed May 16, 2016)

Ciment, James, ed. U.S. Government: Social issues in America: an Encyclopedia. Armonk, NY: M.E. Sharpe, c2006. http://www.loc.gov/catdir/toc/ecip0516/2005018778.html Web. (Accessed 15 May, 2016)

Crimmins, James E., "Jeremy Bentham", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2015 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2015/entries/bentham/ (Accessed Jun 6, 2016)

De Waal, Frans. Moral behavior in animals. Video on TED (Filmed Nov 2011. Posted Apr 2012) New York: TED Conferences LLC., 2012. http://www.ted.com/talks/frans_de_waal_do_animals_have_morals.html/ Web. (Accessed 15 May, 2016)

De Waal, Frans. "The animal roots of human morality." New Scientist 192, no. 2573 (October 14, 2006): 60-61. Academic Search Complete, EBSCOhost http://proxy.lib.sfu.ca/login?url=http://search.ebscohost.com/login.aspx?direct=true&db=a9h&AN=22838055&site=ehost-live Web. (Accessed May 16, 2016).

Einstein, Albert. The Laws of Science and the Laws of Ethics (Preface to Phillipp, Frank Relativity.) A Richer Truth, 1950, Re-Printed in Out of My Later Years, 1950. (pp. 114-115) Humanist Anthology: From Confucius to Attenborough. Margaret Knight, ed. New York: Prometheus Books, 1995 (pp. 158-160). Print.

Emerson, Ralph Waldo. The Spiritual Emerson: Essential Writings. Robinson, David M. ed. Boston: Beacon Press. 2004. (p.250) Print.

Encyclopaedia Britannica. Sir Joseph Rotblat: British physicist and philanthropist. Biography. Updated 1/13/2016. Chicago. http://www.britannica.com/biography/Joseph-Rotblat/ Web. (Accessed May 16, 2016).

Erikson, Erik. H. Childhood and Society. New York: W.W. Norton & Co., 1985. (p. 286) Print.

95

Feynman, Richard. “Biography” Peace Prize Laureates. Nobel Peace Prize 1965. Nobel Media AB 2016. http://www.nobelprize.org/nobel_prizes/physics/laureates/1965/feynman-bio.html/ Web. (Accessed May 16, 2016)

Feynman, Richard. “Facts.” Peace Prize Laureates. Nobel Peace Prize 1965. Nobel Media AB 2016. http://www.nobelprize.org/nobel_prizes/physics/laureates/1965/feynman-facts.html/ Web. (Accessed May 16, 2016)

Feynman, Richard. “The Pleasure of Finding things out”. Video Interview. British Broadcasting Corporation. BBC Horizon Series. http://www.bbc.co.uk/programmes/p018dvyg/ (Min:16:00 to 20:48) Web. (Accessed May 16, 2016)

Feynman, Richard P. The Pleasure of Finding things out. The Best Short Works of Richard P. Feynman. Jeffrey Robbins, ed. New York. Helix Books – Basic Books. 1999. Print. (p. 9-11)

Feynman, Richard. “What Do You Care What Other People Think?”: Further Adventures of a Curious Character. Ralph Leighton, ed. New York: W. W. Norton & Co. 1988. (p. 25) Print.

Fields, A. Belden, and Narr, Wolf-Dieter. “Human Rights as a Holistic Concept.” Human Rights Quarterly Vol. 14, No. 1 (Feb., 1992), (pp. 1-20) 1992. The Johns Hopkins University Press.

Gleick, James. Genius: The Life and Science of Richard Feynman. New York: Vintage. 1993. Print. cited in http://www.nobel-winners.com/Physics/richard_phillips_feynman.html/ Web. (Accessed May 16, 2016)

Government of Canada. Statistics Canada. Crime and Justice. http://www.statcan.gc.ca/dai-quo/ssi/homepage/rel-com/theme2693-eng.htm (Accessed May 16, 2016)

Gowans, Chris, "Moral Relativism", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2012 Edition), Edward N. Zalta., ed. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2012/entries/moral-relativism/ Web. (Accessed May 16, 2016)

96

Greve, Marit. Fridtjof Nansen. Margaret Ellson Davies., trans. Oslo: Aschehoug.1994. Print. Cited in Nansen, Fridtjof. Polar Explorers. Fram Museum, Oslo, Norway. http://www.frammuseum.no/Polar-Heroes/Main-Heroes/Fridtjof-Nansen.aspx/ Web. (Accessed May 16, 2016)

Grimes, William. “Obituary: Antony Flew, Philosopher and Ex-Atheist, Dies at 87.” New York: The New York Times Company. Published April 16, 2010. http://www.nytimes.com/2010/04/17/arts/17flew.html?_r=0/ Web. (Accessed May 16, 2016)

Habermas, Jürgen. et al. An Awareness of What Is Missing. Faith and Reason in a Post-Secular Age. Trans: Cronin, Ciaran. Cambridge: Polity Press, 2010. (pp.18, 19) Print.

Hanna, Peggy. Patriotism, Peace and Vietnam: A Memoir. Ohio: Springfield. Left to Write. 2007. (pp.113-115). Print.

Hijiya, James A. "The Gita of J. Robert Oppenheimer." Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society 144 (2). June 2000. Archived from the original on May 15, 2013. Retrieved December 16, 2013. https://amphilsoc.org/sites/default/files/proceedings/Hijiya.pdf Web. (Accessed May 16, 2016)

Hill, Kit. Professor Pugwash: The Man Who Fought Nukes. U.K. Ryelands Publishing, 2008. Print.

Hinde, Robert A, and Rotblat, Joseph. War No More: Eliminating Conflict in the Nuclear Age. London and Sterling, Va.: Pluto Press., 2003. Print.

Hollinger, David A. "Afterward". In Carson, Cathryn; Hollinger, David A. Reappraising Oppenheimer: Centennial Studies and Reflections. Berkeley, California: Office for History of Science and Technology, Univ. of California. 2005. (385–390).

Institute for Economics and Peace. Global Peace Index. 2016. http://www.visionofhumanity.org/#/page/our-gpi-findings/ Web. (Accessed June 6, 2016)

Jones. G.O. Joseph Rotblat Obituary. Aug 31, 2005. The Guardian News. Sept. 2, 2005. Guardian News and Media Limited. 2016. http://www.theguardian.com/science/2005/sep/02/obituaries.obituaries (Accessed May 16, 2016)

97

Jungk, Robert. Brighter than a Thousand Suns: A Personal History of the Atomic Scientists. New York: Harcourt Brace. 1958. (p.201) Print.

Kant, Immanuel. “An Answer to the Question: What is Enlightenment?” Konigsberg in Prussia, 30 September 1784. https://www.aub.edu.lb/fas/cvsp/Documents/reading_selections/CVSP 203/Fall 13-14/What is Enlightenment - Immanuel kant.pdf/ Web. (Accessed May 16, 2016)

Karnow. Stanley. Vietnam, a History. New York: Penguin Books, 1997. (p.271) Print.

Lingis, Alphonso. The Community of Those Who Have Nothing in Common. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, c1994. (p.159) Print.

Maathai, Wangari. “Biographical.” Peace Prize Laureates. Nobel Peace Prize Laureate. 2004. Nobelprize.org. Nobel Media AB 2016. Web. 12 Jan 2016. http://www.nobelprize.org/nobel_prizes/peace/laureates/2004/maathai-bio.html (Accessed May 16, 2016)

Maathai, Wangari. “Facts.” Peace Prize Laureates. Nobel Peace Prize. 2004. Nobel Media AB 2016. http://www.nobelprize.org/nobel_prizes/peace/laureates/2004/maathai-facts.html Web. (Accessed May 16, 2016)

Maathai, Wangari. Replenishing The Earth: Spiritual Values For Healing Ourselves And The World. Random House Inc. 2010. (pp, 14-15) Print.

Marshall, Dan. Female Genital Mutilation, Religious Rights, and Religious Praxis; Humanity Betrayed: Canadian Law as Humane Intervention. July 29,1998. Unpublished.

Marshall, Dan. Universal Declaration of Human Responsibilities. An Addendum to: The United Nations Universal Declaration of Human Rights. November 9, 1999. Unpublished.

McNamara, Robert S. In Retrospect: The Tragedy and Lessons of Vietnam. New York: Vintage Books. 1996. Print. Cited in Morris, Errol. The Fog of War. Documentary. December 19, 2003/ cited in the New York Times: New York Times Company. http://www.nytimes.com/2009/07/07/us/07mcnamara.html?pagewanted=all Web. (Accessed May 16, 2016)

98

Monk, Ray. Robert Oppenheimer: A Life Inside the Center. New York; Toronto: Doubleday. 2012. (pp. 456–457) Print.

Morris, Errol. The Fog of War: Eleven Lessons from the Life of Robert S. McNamara. Documentary Film. December 19, 2003 http://www.errolmorris.com/film/fow_transcript.html/ Cited in the New York Times Online. Web. (Accessed May 16, 2016)

Nansen, Fridtjof. “Biography.” Peace Prize Laureates. Nobel Peace Prize Laureate 1922. Sweden: Nobel Media AB 2016 http://www.nobelprize.org/nobel_prizes/peace/laureates/1922/nansen-bio.html Web. (Accessed May 16, 2016)

Nansen, Fridtjof. “Press Release.” Peace Prize Laureates. Nobel Peace Prize Laureate 1922. Sweden: Nobel Media AB 2016 http://www.nobelprize.org/nobel_prizes/peace/laureates/1922/press.html/ Web. (Accessed May 16, 2016)

Nansen, Fridtjof. "Science and the Purpose of Life." Speech published by the Rationalist Press Association, 1909, cited in A Biographical Dictionary of Modern Rationalists. https://ffrf.org/news/day/dayitems/item/14590-fridtjof-nansen. Web. (Accessed May 16, 2016)

Nietzsche, Friedrich. Beyond Good and Evil. New York: Vintage Books, 1966, (Ch.1, par. 4, p.11) Print.

Oppenheimer, Robert J. "Now I am become death..." Television Broadcast 1965. The Decision to Drop the Bomb. National Science Digital Library. 2015. San Diego: AJ Software & Multimedia. http://www.atomicarchive.com/Movies/Movie8.shtml/ Web. (Accessed May 16, 2016)

Perls, Friedrich S., M.D., Ph.D. 1969. In and Out The Garbage Pail. Lafayette, California: Real People Press. 1969. Print. (Out of Print) No Page Numbers.

Pew Research Center. “Global Views on Morality.” Global Attitudes and Trends. 2013. Washington DC. Published 2014/4/15 http://www.pewglobal.org/2014/04/15/global-morality/ Web. (Accessed May 16, 2016)

Pew Research Center. “The Future of World Religions: Population Growth Projections, 2010-2050” Demographic Study. 2015. Washington DC. Published 2015/04/03. http://www.pewforum.org/2015/04/02/religious-projections-2010-2050/ Web. (Accessed June 3, 2016)

99

Pew Research Center. “US Public Becoming Less Religious” Global Attitudes and Trends. 2015. Washington DC. Published 2015/11/03. http://www.pewforum.org/2015/11/03/u-s-public-becoming-less-religious/ Web. (Accessed May 16, 2016)

Pugwash Conferences on Science and World Affairs. London: U.K. 2015. http://pugwash.org/ Web. (Accessed May 16, 2016)

Rotblat, Joseph. & Ikeda, Daisaku. A Quest for Global Peace: Rotblat and Ikeda on War, Ethics, and the Nuclear Threat. London: I. B. Tauris, c2007. (p.104) Print.

Rotblat, Joseph. “Facts.” Peace Prize Laureates: Nobel Peace Prize Laureate 1995. Sweden: Nobel Media AB. 2016 http://www.nobelprize.org/nobel_prizes/peace/laureates/1995/rotblat-facts.html Web. (Accessed May 16, 2016)

Rotblat, Joseph. “How to get rid of Nuclear Weapons.” Vancouver Institute. University of British Columbia. UBC Library Open Collections. March 1, 1997. Video recording http://www.library.ubc.ca/archives/institute/vaninst9.html (Accessed May 31, 2016)

Rotblat, Joseph. “Leaving the Bomb Project.” Bulletin of Atomic Scientists. August, 1985. (pp.16-19) Print.

Rotblat, Joseph. “Science and Human Values.” World Conference on Science in Budapest. 10 June 1999. http://britishpugwash.org/wp/wp-content/uploads/2003/11/ScienceandHumanValues.pdf (Accessed May 16, 2016)

Rousseau, Jean-Jacques. The Social Contract and Discourses. G.D.H. Cole., trans. London and Toronto: J.M. Dent and Sons, 1923. (p. 203) Print.

Simon Fraser University. “Peace and the Environment: A Symposium Exploring the Legacy and Insights of Six Nobel Peace Prize Laureates.” Simon Fraser University Institute for the Humanities. The J.S. Woodsworth Chair in the Humanities. (Dr. Eleanor Stebner) Feb 6 & 7, 2014. http://blogs.sfu.ca/departments/humanities-institute/?p=2829 (Accessed May 16, 2016)

Strobel, Lee. Antony Flew on God and Atheism. Video Interview. California: San Bruno. Youtube Inc. Feb 11, 2013. https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=VHUtMEru4pQ/ Web. (Accessed May 16, 2016)

100

Taylor, Charles. A Secular Age. Cambridge, Massachusetts, and London, England. The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. 2007. (p.27) Print.

The Bible: Authorized King James Version. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press, 2008. Print.

The Concise Oxford Dictionary, J.B. Sykes ed. Seventh Edition. UK: Oxford at the Clarendon Press.1988. Print.

United Nations. Declaration on the Right and Responsibility of Individuals, Groups and Organs of Society to Promote and Protect Universally Recognized Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms. Adopted by General Assembly resolution 53/144 of 9 December 1998. Office of the United Nations High Commissioner for Human Rights (OHCHR). http://www.ohchr.org/en/professionalinterest/Pages/RightandResponsibility.aspx Web. (Accessed 14 July, 2016)

United Nations. History of the United Nations. https://www.un.org/en/aboutun/history/ Web. (Accessed May 16, 2016)

United Nations. International Human Rights Law. Office of the United Nations High Commissioner for Human Rights. (OHCHR) http://www.ohchr.org/en/professionalinterest/Pages/InternationalLaw.aspx/ Web. (Accessed May 17, 2016)

United Nations. The Universal Declaration of Human Rights. United Nations General Assembly in Paris on 10 December 1948 http://www.un.org/en/universal declaration-human-rights/ Web. (Accessed May 16, 2016)

United Nations. United Nations Global Issues. 2016. http://www.un.org/en/globalissues/ Web. (Accessed May 16, 2016)

United Nations. What are Human Rights? Office of the United Nations High Commissioner for Human Rights (OHCHR). http://www.ohchr.org/EN/Issues/Pages/WhatareHumanRights.aspx/ Web. (Accessed 15 May, 2016)

United States National Academies of Science, Engineering, and Medicine, The Institute of Medicine (IOM.) Report: Veterans and Agent Orange: Update 2010. September 29, 2011. Last Updated: 8/19/2015. http://iom.nationalacademies.org/reports/2011/veterans-and-agent-orange-update-2010.aspx/ Web. (Accessed May 16, 2016)

101

University of British Columbia. Latin Dictionary. “Educate.” (http://www.math.ubc.ca/~cass/frivs/latin/latin-dict-full.html#E/ Web. (Accessed May 16, 2016)

U.S. Federal Bureau of Investigation. Crime in the United States 2012. https://www.fbi.gov/about-us/cjis/ucr/crime-in-the-u.s/2011/crime-in-the-u.s.-2011/tables/table-1/ Web. (Accessed May 16, 2016)

Weiner, Tim. Robert S. McNamara, Architect of a Futile War, Dies at 93 Cited in New York Times Newspaper. The New York Times Company. July 6, 2009. http://www.nytimes.com/2009/07/07/us/07mcnamara.html?pagewanted=all&_r=0 Web. (Accessed May 16, 2016)

Winter, Jay. “Human Rights and European Remembrance.” Chapter in Memory and Theory in Eastern Europe. Uilleam Blacker, Alexander Etkind, Julie Fedor, eds. Palgrave Studies in Cultural and Intellectual History. US: Palgrave Macmillan. 2013. (Ch. 2. pp 43-58)

102

Works Read

Armstrong, Karen. “The Myth of Religious Violence.” Article in the Guardian News, U.K. Thursday 25 September 2014. Excerpted by the author from Fields of Blood: Religion and the History of Violence. Knopf Canada; First Edition. (Oct. 28, 2014) http://www.theguardian.com/world/2014/sep/25/-sp-karen-armstrong-religious-violence-myth-secular/ Web. (Accessed May 16, 2016)

Aslan, Reza. Beyond Fundamentalism: Confronting Religious Extremism in the Age of Globalization. New York: Random House. 2010. Print.

Bai, Heesoon., Eppert, Claudia., Nguyen, Tram Truon Anh., and Vokey, Daniel. “Intercultural Philosophy and the Nondual Wisdom of ‘Basic Goodness’: Implications for Contemplative and Transformative Education.” Journal of Philosophy of Education, Vol. 49, No. 2, 2015. Oxford: John Wiley & Sons. (pp.274 – 293)

Brill, E.J. Benedictus de Spinoza, Tractatus Theologico-Politicus: Gebhardt Edition 1925. New York: Leiden. 1989. Print.

Charlesworth, James H. ed. The Old Testament Pseudepigrapha. Vol. 1. Apocalyptic Literature and Testaments. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. 1983. Print.

Charlesworth, James H. ed. The Old Testament Pseudepigrapha. Vol. 2. Expansions of the "Old Testament" and Legends, Wisdom and Philosophical Literature, Prayers, Psalms and Odes, Fragments of Lost Judeo-Hellenistic Works.. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. 1985. Print.

Cox, Damian., La Caze, Marguerite., and Levine, Michael. “Integrity.” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2012 Edition) Edward N. Zalta, ed. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2012/entries/integrity/ Web. (Accessed May 16, 2016)

Devlin, Patrick. The Enforcement of Morals. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 1965. Print.

De Waal, Frans, ed. Evolved Morality: The Biology and Philosophy of Human Conscience. Leiden, NLD: BRILL, 2014. ProQuest ebrary. Web. 16 May 2016.http://site.ebrary.com.proxy.lib.sfu.ca/lib/sfu/detail.action?docID=10846294/ Web. (Accessed May 16, 2016)

103

Einstein, Albert, & Freud, Sigmund. 1989. Why War? (Warum Krieg?) An exchange of letters between Albert Einstein and Sigmund Freud. 1st. Edited by Paris: Institute of International Cooperation of the League of Nations, 1932; Ottowa: Shalom Press International, Print.

Fish, Stanley. “Does Reason Know What It Is Missing?” NY: New York Times Company, April 12, 2010. http://opinionator.blogs.nytimes.com/2010/04/12/does-reason-know-what-it-is-missing/ Web. (Accessed May 16, 2016)

Frankl, Viktor E. Man’s Search for Meaning: An Introduction to Logotherapy 4th Edition. Boston: Beacon Press. 1992. Print.

Freud, Sigmund. “Beyond the Pleasure Principle.” In Beyond the Pleasure Principle: Group Psychology and Other Works., Strachey, James, & Freud, Anna. trans. London: Hogarth Press, 1920 - 1922. Toronto: Clark, Irwin & Co., 1962. Print.

Freud, Sigmund. Moses and Monotheism. New York, Hogarth Press. 1939. Print.

Government of Canada. Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms. Constitution Act, (Canada Act 1982.) http://laws-lois.justice.gc.ca/eng/const/page-15.html/ Web. (Accessed May 16, 2016)

Government of Canada. Criminal Code (R.S.C., 1985, c. C-46). Act current to 2016-01-25 and last amended on 2015-07-23. http://laws-lois.justice.gc.ca/eng/acts/C-46/ Web. (Accessed May 16, 2016)

Hoffman, Bruce “Holy Terror: The Implications of Terrorism Motivated by a Religious Imperative,” Studies in Conflict and Terrorism, Vol. 18, No. 4 (1995), (pp. 271-284).

King, L.W. Trans. The Code of Hammurabi. New Haven: Lillian Goldman Law Library. The Avalon Project. 2008. http://avalon.law.yale.edu/subject_menus/hammenu.asp/ Web.

Kohlberg, L. & Turiel, E. Lawrence Kohlberg's Approach to Moral Education. New York: Columbia University Press. 1971. Print.

Kohlberg, Lawrence. The Psychology of Moral Development the Nature and Validity of Moral Stages. San Francisco: Harper & Row. c1984. Print.

104

Kolodny, Niko and Brunero, John, "Instrumental Rationality", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. (Spring 2016 Edition), Edward N. Zalta, ed. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2016/entries/rationality-instrumental/ Web. (Accessed May 16, 2016)

Lessing, Doris. Prisons We Choose To Live Inside. London: Cape, 1987, c1986. Print.

Lyman, D., Jun, A.M. The Moral Sayings of Publius Syrus, a Roman Slave. From the Latin. Cleveland: L.E. Barnard & Company. 1856. Print.

Martin, L.H. et al. “Technologies of the Self.” in Technologies of the Self: A Seminar with Michel Foucault. London: Tavistock. 2008. (pp.16-49) Print.

Milgram, Stanley. Obedience to authority: an experimental view. New York: Harper & Row. 1974. Print.

Nietzsche, Friedrich. On the Genealogy of Morality. Ansell-Pearson, Keith; Diethe, Carol.

trans. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2007. Print.

Orwell, George. “Politics and the English Language.” Horizon: A Review of Literature and Art. (UK: London) Volume 13, Issue 76 April 1946. Print. (pp.252-265)

Piaget, J. The moral judgment of the child. The Free Press: New York. 1932/1965. Print.

Power, F. C., Higgins, A., & Kohlberg, L. The moral judgment of the child. The Free Press: New York. 1989. Print.

Prince, J. Dyneley. “Review: The Code of Hammurabi.” The American Journal of Theology. Vol. 8, No. 3 Jul., 1904, Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. (pp. 601-609)

Reuter, Christoph. “The Prophet's Curse: Islam's Ancient Divide Fuels Middle East Conflicts.“ Spiegel Online 2012. Sept. 6, 2012. http://www.spiegel.de/international/world/how-islam-s-ancient-sectarian-divide-fuels-conflict-in-the-middle-east-a-854106.html/ Web. (Accessed May 16, 2016)

Schopenhauer, Arthur. Religion: a Dialogue (1851). T. B. Saunders., trans. 2nd ed. London: Sonnenschein & Co. 1890. Print.

105

Spinoza, Baruch (Benedict de Spinoza.) 1632-1677 The Ethics (Ethica Ordine Geometrico Demonstrata).Translated from the Latin by R. H. M. Elwes. c.1655-1656. http://www.gutenberg.org/ebooks/3800?msg=welcome_stranger/ Web.

Taylor, Charles. The Ethics of Authenticity. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1989.

(p.5) Print.

United Nations. Current Peacekeeping Operations. 16 January, 2016.

http://www.un.org/en/peacekeeping/operations/current.shtml Web. (Accessed

May 16, 2016)

United Nations. Peacekeeping. http://www.un.org/en/peacekeeping/ Web. (Accessed

May 16, 2016)

U.S. Bureau of Justice Statistics (BJS), “Prisoners in 2013.” E. Ann Carson, Ph.D.

September 16, 2014. NCJ 247282

http://www.bjs.gov/index.cfm?ty=pbdetail&iid=5109/ Web. (Accessed May 16,

2016)

Van Seters, John. “The Pentateuch”. In Steven L. McKenzie & Matt Patrick Graham. The

Hebrew Bible today: an introduction to critical issues. Westminster: John Knox

Press. 1998. Print.

Wainwright, William J. “Religion and Morality. 1st ed.” Ashgate philosophy of religion series. Burlington, VT, USA: Ashgate Publishing Company. 2005. Print.

Wright, David P. Inventing God's law how the covenant code of the Bible used and revised the Laws of Hammurabi. New York: Oxford University Press, 2009. University of British Columbia Library. Online. Restricted access UBC Library.

Zaslove, Jerald. Notes On Utopia And Beauty As Social Imaginaries: Ideology And

Consciousness In Action. Unpublished Paper. n.d.


Recommended