+ All Categories
Home > Documents > UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre...

UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre...

Date post: 11-Jul-2020
Category:
Upload: others
View: 0 times
Download: 0 times
Share this document with a friend
104
UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of Psychology and Economics (219A) Module I: Choice under Uncertainty
Transcript
Page 1: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

UC BerkeleyDepartment of Economics

Foundations of Psychology and Economics (219A)

Module I: Choice under Uncertainty

Page 2: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Reading list

1. Camerer, C. (1995) “Individual Decision Making,” in Handbook of Exper-imental Economics. J. Kagel and A. Roth, eds. Princeton U. Press.

2. Starmer, C. (2000) “Developments in Non-Expected Utility Theory: TheHunt for a descriptive Theory of Choice under Risk,” Journal of EconomicLiterature, 38, pp. 332-382.

3. Harless, D. and C. Camerer (1994) “The Predictive Utility of GeneralizedExpected Utility Theories,” Econometrica, 62, pp. 1251-1289.

Page 3: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of ExpectedUtility Theory Using Experimental Data,” Econometrica, 62, pp. 1291-1326.

5. Holt, C. and S. Laury (2002) “Risk Aversion and Incentive Effects,” Amer-ican Economic Review, 92, pp. 1644-1655.

6. Choi, S., R. Fisman, D. Gale, and S. Kariv (2007) “Consistency and Het-erogeneity of Individual Behavior under Uncertainty,” American EconomicReview, 97, pp. 1921-1938.

7. Halevy, Y. (2007) “Ellsberg Revisited: An Experimental Study”, Econo-metrica, 75, pp. 503-536.

Page 4: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Background

• Decisions under uncertainty enter every realm of economic decision-making.

• Models of choice under uncertainty play a key role in every field of eco-nomics.

• Test the empirical validity of particular axioms or to compare the predictiveabilities of competing theories.

Page 5: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Experiments à la Allais

• Each theory predicts indifference curves with distinctive shapes in the prob-ability triangle.

• By choosing alternatives that theories rank differently, each theory can betested against the others.

• The criterion typically used to evaluate a theory is the fraction of choicesit predicts correctly.

Page 6: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Allais (1953) I

— Choose between the two gambles:

$25, 000.33%

A :=.66−→ $24, 000 B :=

1−→ $24, 000&.01

$0

Page 7: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Allais (1953) II

— Choose between the two gambles:

$25, 000 $24, 000.33%

.34%

C := D :=&.067

&.066

$0 $0

Page 8: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

The Marschak-Machina probability triangle

1

HP

Increasing preference

LP 0

1

H, M, and L are three degenerate gambles with certain outcomes H>M>L

Page 9: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

A violation of Expected Utility Theory (EUT)

A

B

CD

1

HP

LP 0

1

EUT requires that indifference lines are parallel so one must choose either A and C, or B and D.

Page 10: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Contributions

Results have generated the most impressive dialogue between observationand theorizing:

— Violations of EUT raise criticisms about the status of the Savage axiomsas the touchstone of rationality.

— These criticisms have generated the development of various alternativesto EUT, such as Prospect Theory.

Page 11: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Results have generated the most impressive dialogue between observationand theorizing (Camerer, 1995):

— ...EU violations are much smaller (though still statistically significant)when subjects choose between gambles that all lie inside the triangle...

— ...due to nonlinear weighting of the probabilities near zero (as the rankdependent weighting theories and prospect theory predict)...

— ...the only theories that can explain the evidence of mixed fanning,violation of betweeness, and approximate EU maximization inside thetriangle...

Page 12: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Rank-dependent expected utility (Quiggin, 1982)

Index consequences (x1, ..., xn) such that x1 is the worst and xn is thebest.

The weights for i = 1, ..., n− 1 are give by:

ωi = π(pi + · · ·+ pn)− π(pi+1 + · · ·+ pn)

and ωn = π(pn).

The predictions of the model depend crucially on the form of π(·). Onepossibility is an (inverted) S-shaped probability weighting function.

Page 13: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Limitations

Choice scenarios narrowly tailored to reveal anomalies limits the usefulnessof data for other purposes:

— Subjects face extreme rather than typical decision problems designedto encourage violations of specific axioms.

— Small data sets force experimenters to pool data and to ignore individ-ual heterogeneity.

Page 14: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Research questions

Consistency

— Is behavior under uncertainty consistent with the utility maximizationmodel?

Structure

— Is behavior consistent with a utility function with some special struc-tural properties?

Page 15: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Recoverability

— Can the underlying utility function be recovered from observed choices?

Heuristics

— Can heuristic procedures be identified when they occur?

Page 16: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

A new experimental design

An experimental design that has a couple of fundamental innovations overprevious work:

— A selection of a bundle of contingent commodities from a budget set(a portfolio choice problem).

— A graphical experimental interface that allows for the collection of arich individual-level data set.

Page 17: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

The experimental computer program dialog windows

Page 18: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental
Page 19: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

• The choice of a portfolio subject to a budget constraint provides moreinformation about preferences than a binary choice.

• A large menu of decision problems that are representative, in the statisticalsense and in the economic sense.

• A rich dataset that provides the opportunity to interpret the behavior atthe level of the individual subject.

Page 20: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Rationality

Let {(pi, xi)}50i=1 be some observed individual data (pi denotes the i-thobservation of the price vector and xi denotes the associated portfolio).

A utility function u(x) rationalizes the observed behavior if it achieves themaximum on the budget set at the chosen portfolio

u(xi) ≥ u(x) for all x s.t. pi · xi ≥ pi · x.

Page 21: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Revealed preference

A portfolio xi is directly revealed preferred to a portfolio xj if pi · xi ≥pi · xj, and xi is strictly directly revealed preferred to xj if the inequalityis strict.

The relation indirectly revealed preferred is the transitive closure of thedirectly revealed preferred relation.

Page 22: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Generalized Axiom of Revealed Preference (GARP) If xi is indirectlyrevealed preferred to xj, then xj is not strictly directly revealed preferred(i.e. pj · xj ≤ pj · xi) to xi.

GARP is tied to utility representation through a theorem, which was firstproved by Afriat (1967).

Page 23: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Afriat’s Theorem The following conditions are equivalent:

— The data satisfy GARP.

— There exists a non-satiated utility function that rationalizes the data.

— There exists a concave, monotonic, continuous, non-satiated utilityfunction that rationalizes the data.

Page 24: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Goodness-of-fit

• Verifying GARP is conceptually straightforward but it can be difficult inpractice.

• Since GARP offers an exact test, it is necessary to measure the extent ofGARP violations.

• Measures of GARP violations based on three indices: Afriat (1972), Varian(1991), and Houtman and Maks (1985).

Page 25: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Afriat’s critical cost efficiency index (CCEI) The amount by whicheach budget constraint must be relaxed in order to remove all violationsof GARP.

The CCEI is bounded between zero and one. The closer it is to one, thesmaller the perturbation required to remove all violations and thus thecloser the data are to satisfying GARP.

Page 26: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

The construction of the CCEI for a simple violation of GARP

2x

1x

D

C

B A

x

y

The agent is ‘wasting' as much as A/B<C/D of his income by making inefficient choices.

Page 27: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

A benchmark level of consistency

A random sample of hypothetical subjects who implement the power utilityfunction

u(x) =x1−ρ

1− ρ,

commonly employed in the empirical analysis of choice under uncertainty,with error.

The likelihood of error is assumed to be a decreasing function of the utilitycost of an error.

Page 28: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

More precisely, we assume an idiosyncratic preference shock that has alogistic distribution

Pr(x∗) =eγ·u(x

∗)Rx:p·x=1

eγ·u(x),

where the precision parameter γ reflects sensitivity to differences in utility.

If utility maximization is not the correct model, is our experiment suffi-ciently powerful to detect it?

Page 29: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

The distributions of GARP violations – ρ=1/2 and different γ

0.00

0.05

0.10

0.15

0.20

0.25

0.30

0.35

0.40

0.45

0.50

0.55

0.60

0.65

0.70

0.75

0.80

0.00

0.05

0.10

0.15

0.20

0.25

0.30

0.35

0.40

0.45

0.50

0.55

0.60

0.65

0.70

0.75

0.80

0.85

0.90

0.95

1.00

CCEI

γ=1/4

γ=1/2

γ=1

γ=5

γ=10

Page 30: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Bronnars’ (1987) test (γ=0)

0.00

0.05

0.10

0.15

0.20

0.25

0.30

0.35

0.40

0.45

0.50

0.55

0.60

0.65

0.70

0.75

0.80

0.00

0.05

0.10

0.15

0.20

0.25

0.30

0.35

0.40

0.45

0.50

0.55

0.60

0.65

0.70

0.75

0.80

0.85

0.90

0.95

1.00

CCEI

n=5

n=15n=50

n=10

n=20

Page 31: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Recoverability

• GARP imposes on the data the complete set of conditions implied byutility-maximization.

• Revealed preference relations in the data thus contain the information thatis necessary for recovering preferences.

• Varian’s (1982) algorithm serves as a partial solution to this so-called re-coverability problem.

Page 32: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Risk neutrality

Page 33: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Infinite risk aversion

Page 34: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Loss / disappointment aversion

Page 35: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

The distributions of GARP violations - Afriat (1972) CCEI

0.00

0.05

0.10

0.15

0.20

0.25

0.30

0.35

0.40

0.45

0.50

0.55

0.60

0.65

0.70

00.0

5 0.1 0.15 0.2 0.25 0.3 0.35 0.4 0.45 0.5 0.55 0.6 0.65 0.7 0.75 0.8 0.85 0.9 0.95 1

Frac

tion

of s

ubje

cts

Actual Random

Page 36: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

The distributions of GARP violations - Varian (1991)

0.00

0.05

0.10

0.15

0.20

0.25

0.30

0.35

0.40

0.45

0.50

0.55

0.60

0.65

0.70

00.0

5 0.1 0.15 0.2 0.25 0.3 0.35 0.4 0.45 0.5 0.55 0.6 0.65 0.7 0.75 0.8 0.85 0.9 0.95 1

Frac

tion

of s

ubje

cts

Actual Random

Page 37: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

The distribution of GARP violations - Houtman and Maks (1985)

0.00

0.05

0.10

0.15

0.20

0.25

0.30

0.35

0 2 4 6 8 10 12 14 16 18 20 22 24 26 28 30 32 34 36 38 40 42 44 46 48 50

Frac

tion

of s

ubje

cts

Actual

Page 38: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Granularity

• A measure of the size of the components, or descriptions of components,that make up a system (Wikipedia).

• There is no taxonomy that allows us to classify all subjects unambiguously.

• A review of the full data set reveals striking regularities within and markedheterogeneity across subjects.

Page 39: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

ID 304 (0 / 1.000 / 50)

Page 40: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

ID 303 (0 / 1.000 / 50)

Page 41: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

ID 309 (17 / 0.952 / 48)

Page 42: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

ID 317 (0 / 1.000/ 50)

Page 43: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

ID 205 (0 / 1.000 / 50)

Page 44: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

ID 307 (12 / 0.916 / 46)

Page 45: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

ID 216 (0 / 1.000 / 50)

Page 46: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

ID 207 (15 / 0.981 / 47)

Page 47: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

ID 327 (5 / 0.965 / 49)

Page 48: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

ID 213 (0 / 1.000 / 50)

Page 49: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Risk aversion

A “low-tech” approach of estimating an individual-level power utility func-tion directly from the data:

u(x) =x1−ρ

(1− ρ).

ρ is the Arrow-Pratt measure of relative risk aversion. The aversion to riskincreases as ρ increases.

Page 50: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

This generates the following individual-level econometric specification foreach subject n:

log

Ãxi2nxi1n

!= αn + βn log

Ãpi1npi2n

!+ i

n

where in ∼ N(0, σ2n).

We generate estimates of ρ̂n = 1/β̂n which allows us to test for hetero-geneity of risk preferences.

Page 51: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

The distribution of the individual Arrow-Pratt measures (OLS)

0.00

0.02

0.04

0.06

0.08

0.10

0.12

0.14

0.16

0.18

0.20

0.22

0.24

0.0 0.2 0.4 0.6 0.8 1.0 1.2 1.4 1.6 1.8 2.0 2.2 2.4 2.6 2.8 3.0 3.2 3.4 3.6 3.8 4.0 4.2 4.4 4.6 4.8 5.0 5.2 5.4 5.6 5.8 6.0Fr

actio

n of

sub

ject

s

OLS

Page 52: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Loss/disappointment aversion

The theory of Gul (1991) implies that the utility function over portfoliostakes the form

min {αu (x1) + u (x2) , u (x1) + αu (x2)} ,

where α ≥ 1 measures loss/disappointment aversion and u(·) is the utilityof consumption in each state.

If α > 1 there is a kink at the point where x1 = x2 and if α = 1 we havethe standard EUT representation.

Page 53: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

An illustration of the derived demand

2

1lnxx

2

1lnpp

0ln2

1 =xx

0ln2

1 =pp

Page 54: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

The indifference map of Gul (1991)

1

HP

LP

1

Page 55: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Scatterplot of the estimated CRRA parameters

0.0

0.2

0.4

0.6

0.8

1.0

1.2

1.4

1.6

1.8

2.0

2.2

2.4

2.6

2.8

3.0

3.2

3.4

3.6

3.8

4.0

1.0 1.2 1.4 1.6 1.8 2.0 2.2 2.4 2.6 2.8 3.0 3.2 3.4 3.6 3.8 4.0α

ρ

Page 56: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

The risk premium r(1) for different values of α and ρ

0.0

0.1

0.2

0.3

0.4

0.5

0.6

0.7

0.8

0.9

1.0

0.0 0.1 0.2 0.3 0.4 0.5 0.6 0.7 0.8 0.9h

r(h)

α=1, ρ =0

α=1, ρ =0.5

α=1.5, ρ =0.5

α=1.5, ρ =1.5

Page 57: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Scatterplot of the risk measures – power and loss/disappointment

0.0

0.2

0.4

0.6

0.8

1.0

1.2

1.4

1.6

1.8

2.0

2.2

2.4

2.6

2.8

3.0

3.2

3.4

3.6

3.8

4.0

0.0 0.2 0.4 0.6 0.8 1.0 1.2 1.4 1.6 1.8 2.0 2.2 2.4 2.6 2.8 3.0 3.2 3.4 3.6 3.8 4.0r (1)

ρ

Page 58: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Ambiguity

• The distinction between settings with risk and ambiguity dates back to atleast the work of Knight (1921).

• Ellsberg (1961) countered the reduction of subjective uncertainty to riskwith several thought experiments.

• A large theoretical literature (axioms over preferences) has developed mod-els to accommodate this behavior.

• But what matters most is the implications of the models for choice behav-ior.

Page 59: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Ellsberg (1961)

An urn contains 300 marbles; 100 of the marbles are red, and 200 aresome mixture of blue and green. We will reach into this urn and select amarble at random:

— You receive $25, 000 if the marble selected is of a specified color.Would you rather the color be red or blue?

— You receive $25, 000 if the marble selected is not of a specified color.Would you rather the color be red or blue?

Page 60: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Consider the following two-color Ellsberg-type urns (Halevy, 2007):

I. 5 red balls and 5 black balls

II. an unknown number of red and black

III. a bag containing 11 tickets with the numbers 0-10; the number writtenon the drawn ticket determines the number of red balls

IV. a bag containing 2 tickets with the numbers 0 and 10; the numberwritten on the drawn ticket determines the number of red balls.

Page 61: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

• A clever experiment to verify the connection between the reduction ofobjective compound lotteries and attitudes to ambiguity.

• Four different urns are used to elicit choices in the presence of risk, ambi-guity, and two degrees of compound uncertainty.

• Different models generate different predictions about how the reservationvalues (BDM) for these four urns will be ordered.

• The experiment can therefore classify each subject according to whichmodel predicts his ordering of reservation values.

Page 62: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

• Now, consider three states of nature and corresponding Arrow security(pays one dollar in one state and nothing in the other states).

• One state has an objectively known probability, whereas the probabilitiesof the other states are ambiguous.

• The presence of ambiguity could cause not just a departure from EU, buta more fundamental departure from rationality.

• Our analysis suggests otherwise — choices under ambiguity are at least asrationalizable as choices under risk.

Page 63: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

The distributions of CCEI scores

0.00

0.05

0.10

0.15

0.20

0.25

0.30

0.35

0.40

0.45

0.50

0.55

0.60

0.05

0.10

0.15

0.20

0.25

0.30

0.35

0.40

0.45

0.50

0.55

0.60

0.65

0.70

0.75

0.80

0.85

0.90

0.95

1.00

CCEI

Frac

tion

of s

ubje

cts

Risk Ambiguity Random

Page 64: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Structure, recoverability and extrapolation

The conventional parametric approach:

— Choose a parametric form for the underlying utility function and fit theassociated demand function to the data.

— Test to see if they conform to the special restrictions imposed by hy-potheses concerning functional structure.

— Construct an estimate of the underlying utility function and forecastdemand behavior in new situations.

Page 65: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Recursive Expected Utility (REU)

-2.5 -2 -1.5 -1 -0.5 0 0.5 1 1.5 2 2.50

0.1

0.2

0.3

0.4

0.5

0.6

0.7

0.8

0.9

1

log(p1/p3)

x 1/(x 1+

x 3)

The Simulated x1/(x1+x3) and log(p1/p3) in the REU Model when alpha = 0.1

rho = 0.05

rho = 0.10

rho = 0.25rho = 0.5

rho = 1

rho = 2

-2.5 -2 -1.5 -1 -0.5 0 0.5 1 1.5 2 2.50

0.1

0.2

0.3

0.4

0.5

0.6

0.7

0.8

0.9

1

log(p1/p2)

x 1/(x 1+

x 2)

The Simulated x1/(x1+x2) and log(p1/p2) in the REU Model when alpha = 0.1

rho = 0.05

rho = 0.10

rho = 0.25rho = 0.5

rho = 1

rho = 2

-2.5 -2 -1.5 -1 -0.5 0 0.5 1 1.5 2 2.50

0.1

0.2

0.3

0.4

0.5

0.6

0.7

0.8

0.9

1

log(p1/p3)

x 1/(x 1+

x 3)

The Simulated x1/(x1+x3) and log(p1/p3) in the REU Model when alpha = 1

rho = 0.05

rho = 0.10

rho = 0.25rho = 0.5

rho = 1

rho = 2

-2.5 -2 -1.5 -1 -0.5 0 0.5 1 1.5 2 2.50

0.1

0.2

0.3

0.4

0.5

0.6

0.7

0.8

0.9

1

log(p1/p2)

x 1/(x 1+

x 2)

The Simulated x1/(x1+x2) and log(p1/p2) in the REU Model when alpha = 1

rho = 0.05

rho = 0.10

rho = 0.25rho = 0.5

rho = 1

rho = 2

Page 66: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

-2.5 -2 -1.5 -1 -0.5 0 0.5 1 1.5 2 2.50

0.1

0.2

0.3

0.4

0.5

0.6

0.7

0.8

0.9

1

log(p1/p3)

x 1/(x 1+

x 3)

The Simulated x1/(x1+x3) and log(p1/p3) in the REU Model when alpha = 1.75

rho = 0.05

rho = 0.10

rho = 0.25rho = 0.5

rho = 1

rho = 2

-2.5 -2 -1.5 -1 -0.5 0 0.5 1 1.5 2 2.50

0.1

0.2

0.3

0.4

0.5

0.6

0.7

0.8

0.9

1

log(p1/p2)

x 1/(x 1+

x 2)

The Simulated x1/(x1+x2) and log(p1/p2) in the REU Model when alpha = 1.75

rho = 0.05

rho = 0.10

rho = 0.25rho = 0.5

rho = 1

rho = 2

-2.5 -2 -1.5 -1 -0.5 0 0.5 1 1.5 2 2.50

0.1

0.2

0.3

0.4

0.5

0.6

0.7

0.8

0.9

1

log(p1/p3)

x 1/(x 1+

x 3)

The Simulated x1/(x1+x3) and log(p1/p3) in the REU Model when alpha = 2

rho = 0.05

rho = 0.10

rho = 0.25rho = 0.5

rho = 1

rho = 2

-2.5 -2 -1.5 -1 -0.5 0 0.5 1 1.5 2 2.50

0.1

0.2

0.3

0.4

0.5

0.6

0.7

0.8

0.9

1

log(p1/p2)

x 1/(x 1+

x 2)

The Simulated x1/(x1+x2) and log(p1/p2) in the REU Model when alpha = 2

rho = 0.05

rho = 0.10

rho = 0.25rho = 0.5

rho = 1

rho = 2

Page 67: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

α-Maxmin Expected Utility (α-MEU)

-2.5 -2 -1.5 -1 -0.5 0 0.5 1 1.5 2 2.50

0.1

0.2

0.3

0.4

0.5

0.6

0.7

0.8

0.9

1

log(p1/p3)

x 1/(x 1+

x 3)

The Simulated x1/(x1+x3) and log(p1/p3) in the Alpha-MEU Model when alpha = 0.55

rho = 0.05

rho = 0.10

rho = 0.25rho = 0.5

rho = 1

rho = 2

-2.5 -2 -1.5 -1 -0.5 0 0.5 1 1.5 2 2.50

0.1

0.2

0.3

0.4

0.5

0.6

0.7

0.8

0.9

1

log(p1/p2)

x 1/(x 1+

x 2)

The Simulated x1/(x1+x2) and log(p1/p2) in the Alpha-MEU Model when alpha = 0.55

rho = 0.05

rho = 0.10

rho = 0.25rho = 0.5

rho = 1

rho = 2

-2.5 -2 -1.5 -1 -0.5 0 0.5 1 1.5 2 2.50

0.1

0.2

0.3

0.4

0.5

0.6

0.7

0.8

0.9

1

log(p1/p3)

x 1/(x 1+

x 3)

The Simulated x1/(x1+x3) and log(p1/p3) in the Alpha-MEU Model when alpha = 0.6

rho = 0.05

rho = 0.10

rho = 0.25rho = 0.5

rho = 1

rho = 2

-2.5 -2 -1.5 -1 -0.5 0 0.5 1 1.5 2 2.50

0.1

0.2

0.3

0.4

0.5

0.6

0.7

0.8

0.9

1

log(p1/p2)

x 1/(x 1+

x 2)

The Simulated x1/(x1+x2) and log(p1/p2) in the Alpha-MEU Model when alpha = 0.6

rho = 0.05

rho = 0.10

rho = 0.25rho = 0.5

rho = 1

rho = 2

Page 68: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

-2.5 -2 -1.5 -1 -0.5 0 0.5 1 1.5 2 2.50

0.1

0.2

0.3

0.4

0.5

0.6

0.7

0.8

0.9

1

log(p1/p3)

x 1/(x 1+

x 3)

The Simulated x1/(x1+x3) and log(p1/p3) in the Alpha-MEU Model when alpha = 0.8

rho = 0.05

rho = 0.10

rho = 0.25rho = 0.5

rho = 1

rho = 2

-2.5 -2 -1.5 -1 -0.5 0 0.5 1 1.5 2 2.50

0.1

0.2

0.3

0.4

0.5

0.6

0.7

0.8

0.9

1

log(p1/p2)

x 1/(x 1+

x 2)

The Simulated x1/(x1+x2) and log(p1/p2) in the Alpha-MEU Model when alpha = 0.8

rho = 0.05

rho = 0.10

rho = 0.25rho = 0.5

rho = 1

rho = 2

-2.5 -2 -1.5 -1 -0.5 0 0.5 1 1.5 2 2.50

0.1

0.2

0.3

0.4

0.5

0.6

0.7

0.8

0.9

1

log(p1/p3)

x 1/(x 1+

x 3)

The Simulated x1/(x1+x3) and log(p1/p3) in the Alpha-MEU Model when alpha = 1

rho = 0.05

rho = 0.10

rho = 0.25rho = 0.5

rho = 1

rho = 2

-2.5 -2 -1.5 -1 -0.5 0 0.5 1 1.5 2 2.50

0.1

0.2

0.3

0.4

0.5

0.6

0.7

0.8

0.9

1

log(p1/p2)

x 1/(x 1+

x 2)

The Simulated x1/(x1+x2) and log(p1/p2) in the Alpha-MEU Model when alpha = 1

rho = 0.05

rho = 0.10

rho = 0.25rho = 0.5

rho = 1

rho = 2

Page 69: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Individual-level data

Page 70: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental
Page 71: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental
Page 72: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Estimation results

Page 73: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental
Page 74: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental
Page 75: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Procedural rationality

• How subjects come to make decisions that are consistent with an underlyingpreference ordering?

• Boundedly rational individuals use heuristics in their attempt to maximizean underlying preference ordering.

— There is a distinction between true underlying preferences and revealedpreferences.

— Preferences have an EU representation, even though revealed prefer-ences appear to be non-EU.

Page 76: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

A type-mixture model (TMM)

A unified account of both procedural rationality and substantive rationality.

— Allow EU maximization to play the role of the underlying preferenceordering.

— Account for subjects’ underlying preferences and their choice of decisionrules.

Page 77: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Ingredients

• The “true” underlying preferences are represented by a power utility func-tion.

• A discrete choice among the fixed set of prototypical heuristics, D, S andB(ω).

• The probability of choosing each particular heuristic is a function of thebudget set.

Page 78: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

• Subjects could make mistakes when trying to maximize EU by employingheuristic S.

• In contrast, when following heuristic D or B(ω) subjects’ hands do nottremble.

• A subject may prefer to choose heuristic B(ω) or D instead of the noisyversion of heuristic S.

Page 79: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Specification

The underlying preferences of each subject are assumed to be representedby

u (x) =x1−ρ

(1− ρ)

(power utility function as long as consumption in each state meets thesecure level ω).

Let ϕ(p) be the portfolio which gives the subject the maximum (expected)utility achievable at given prices p.

Page 80: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

The ex ante expected payoff from attempting to maximize EU by employingheuristic S is given by

US(p) = E[πu (ϕ̃1(p)) + (1− π)u (ϕ̃2(p))]

ϕ̃(p) is a random portfolio s.t. p · ϕ̃(p) = 1 for every p = (p1, p2), andp1[ϕ̃1(p)− ϕ1(p)] = ε and i

n ∼ N(0, σ2n).

Page 81: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

When following heuristic D or B subjects’ hands do not tremble. Wetherefore write

UD (p) = u(1/(p1 + p2))

and

UB (p) = max{πu(0) + (1− π)u(1/p2), πu(1/p1) + (1− π)u(0)}

Page 82: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Estimation

The probability of choosing heuristic k = D,S,B(ω) is given by a stan-dard logistic discrete choice model:

Pr(heuristic τ |p;β, ρ, σ) = eβUτPk=D,S,B

eβUk

where UD, US and UB is the payoff specification for heuristic D, S andB(ω), respectively.

Page 83: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

• The β̂ estimates are significantly positive, implying that the TMM hassome predictive power.

• Most subjects exhibit moderate to high levels of risk preferences aroundρ̂ = 0.8.

• There is a strong correlation between the estimated ρ̂ parameters from“low-tech” OLS and TMM estimations.

Page 84: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

The distribution of the individual Arrow-Pratt measures (TMM)

0.00

0.02

0.04

0.06

0.08

0.10

0.12

0.14

0.16

0.18

0.20

0.22

0.24

0.0 0.2 0.4 0.6 0.8 1.0 1.2 1.4 1.6 1.8 2.0 2.2 2.4 2.6 2.8 3.0 3.2 3.4 3.6 3.8 4.0 4.2 4.4 4.6 4.8 5.0 5.2 5.4 5.6 5.8 6.0Fr

actio

n of

sub

ject

s

TMM

Page 85: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Goodness-of-fit

• Compare the choice probabilities predicted by the TMM and empiricalchoice probabilities.

• Nadaraya-Watson nonparametric estimator with a Gaussian kernel func-tion.

• The empirical data are supportive of the TMM model (fits best in thesymmetric treatment).

Page 86: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Procedural rationality

• How subjects come to make decisions that are consistent with an underlyingpreference ordering?

• Boundedly rational individuals use heuristics in their attempt to maximizean underlying preference ordering.

— There is a distinction between true underlying preferences and revealedpreferences.

— Preferences have an EU representation, even though revealed prefer-ences appear to be non-EU.

Page 87: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Archetypes and polytypes

• We identify a finite number of stylized behaviors, which collectively posea challenge to decision theory.

• We call these basic behaviors archetypes. We also find mixtures of archetypalbehaviors, which we call polytypes.

• The archetypes account for a large proportion of the data set and play arole in the behavior of most subjects.

• The combinations of types defy any of the standard models of risk aversion.

Page 88: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Center

Vertex

Page 89: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Centroid (budget shares)

Edge

Page 90: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Bisector

Center and bisector

Page 91: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Edge and bisector

Center, vertex, and edge

Page 92: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Vertex and edge

Center and bisector

Page 93: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

The aggregate distribution of archetypes for different token confidence intervals

Center Vertex Centroid Edge Bisector All 0.1 0.005 0.003 0.000 0.019 0.083 0.110

0.25 0.061 0.004 0.002 0.083 0.187 0.337

0.5 0.093 0.011 0.007 0.139 0.215 0.466

1 0.134 0.032 0.019 0.165 0.252 0.602

2.5 0.185 0.064 0.049 0.186 0.285 0.769

Page 94: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

The distribution of archetypes, by subject (half token confidence interval)

0.0

0.1

0.2

0.3

0.4

0.5

0.6

0.7

0.8

0.9

1.0

Frac

tion

of d

ecis

ions

Center Vertex Centroid Edge Bisector

Page 95: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

The distribution of archetypes, by subject (one token confidence interval)

0.0

0.1

0.2

0.3

0.4

0.5

0.6

0.7

0.8

0.9

1.0

5 90 22 53 47 46 77 68 63 58 32 12 45 49 98 66 38 91 18 8 95 41 81 88 69 94 75 23 67 7 62 92 57 40

Frac

tion

of d

ecis

ions

Center Vertex Centroid Edge Bisector

Page 96: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

A two- and three-asset experiment Token Shares in 3-asset experiment for Subject ID 3

TS2 = 1

TS1 = 1 TS3 = 1

0 10 20 30 40 50 60 70 80 90 1000

10

20

30

40

50

60

70

80

90

100

The relation of x1 and x2 in 2-asset experiment for ID 3

x1

x 2

Page 97: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Token Shares in 3-asset experiment for Subject ID 47

TS2 = 1

TS1 = 1 TS3 = 1

0 10 20 30 40 50 60 70 80 90 1000

10

20

30

40

50

60

70

80

90

100

The relation of x1 and x2 in 2-asset experiment for ID 47

x1

x 2

Page 98: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Token Shares in 3-asset experiment for Subject ID 25

TS2 = 1

TS1 = 1 TS3 = 1

0 10 20 30 40 50 60 70 80 90 1000

10

20

30

40

50

60

70

80

90

100

The relation of x1 and x2 in 2-asset experiment for ID 25

x1

x 2

Page 99: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Token Shares in 3-asset experiment for Subject ID 61

TS2 = 1

TS1 = 1 TS3 = 1

0 10 20 30 40 50 60 70 80 90 1000

10

20

30

40

50

60

70

80

90

100

The relation of x1 and x2 in 2-asset experiment for ID 61

x1

x 2

Page 100: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Token Shares in 3-asset experiment for Subject ID 65

TS2 = 1

TS1 = 1 TS3 = 1

0 10 20 30 40 50 60 70 80 90 1000

10

20

30

40

50

60

70

80

90

100

The relation of x1 and x2 in 2-asset experiment for ID 65

x1

x 2

Page 101: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Type-mixture model (TMM)

• A subject chooses among the fixed set of types (heuristics), in order toapproximate the behavior that is optimal for his true underlying preferences.

• Consistent behavior requires subjects to choose among heuristics in a con-sistent manner as well as behaving consistently in applying a given heuristic.

• A TMM (CFGK, 2006) combines the distinctive types of behavior observedin the raw data in a coherent theory based on underlying preferences.

• It exhibits significant explanatory power and produces reasonable estimatesof risk aversion.

Page 102: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Discussion

Suppose there are states of nature and associated Arrow securities andthat the agent’s behavior is represented by the decision problem

max u (x)s.t. x ∈ B (p) ∩A

where B (p) is the budget set and A is the set of portfolios correspondingto the various archetypes the agent uses to simplify his choice problem.

The only restriction we have to impose is that A is a pointed cone (closedunder multiplication by positive scalars), which is satisfied ifA is composedof any selection of archetypes except the Centroid.

Page 103: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

We can derive the following properties of the agent’s demand:

1. Let pk denotes the k-th observation of the price vector and

xk ∈ argmaxnu (x) : x ∈ B

³pk´∩A

odenotes the associated portfolio. Then the data

npk,xk

osatisfy

GARP.

2. There exists a utility function u∗ (x) such that for any price vector p,

x∗ ∈ argmax {u (x) : x ∈ B (p) ∩A}⇔

x∗ ∈ argmax {u∗ (x) : x ∈ B (p)} .

Page 104: UC Berkeley Department of Economics Foundations of ...kariv/219A_risk.pdf · 4. Hey, J. and C. Omre (1994) “Investigating Generalizations of Expected Utility Theory Using Experimental

Takeaways

[1] Classical economics assumes that decisions are based on substantive ratio-nality, and has little to say about the procedures by which decisions arereached.

[2] Rather than focusing on the consistency of behavior with non-EUT theo-ries, we study the fine-grained details of individual behaviors in search ofclues to procedural rationality.

[3] The “switching” behavior that is evident in the data leads us to preferan “alternative” approach — one that emphasizes standard preferences andprocedural rationality.


Recommended