+ All Categories
Home > Documents > Chapter one: Introduction to Frege on Thinking and Its Epistemic Significance (coauthored with Nicla...

Chapter one: Introduction to Frege on Thinking and Its Epistemic Significance (coauthored with Nicla...

Date post: 24-Feb-2023
Category:
Upload: umn-morris
View: 0 times
Download: 0 times
Share this document with a friend
43
1 Chapter One Introduction This book proposes an analysis of the notion of thinking (das Denken) in Gottlob Frege and argues that this notion has not been sufficiently investigated. In fact, the term “thinking” is disregarded so much as to be forgotten: it does not even deserve to be mentioned in the index of Michael Dummett’s Frege: Philosophy of Language and it does not appear in the indexes of the books of some well-known critics of Dummett such as Hans Sluga or Gregory Currie.1 This is not surprising given the influence of the conviction that the study of thinking is psychological and thus of no interest to logic. It is widely believed that Frege did not regard human mental processes as philosophically relevant because of his often declared anti-psychologism. However, this reading does not explain why Frege says so much about thinking both in his earlier writings such as Begriffsschrift (1879) and “On the Scientific Justification for a Conceptual Notation” (1882), and in his later works such as “Der Gedanke” (1918-1919) and “Sources of Knowledge of Mathematics and the Mathematical Natural Sciences” (1924-1925). As a matter of fact, Frege devoted much attention to human mental processes and
Transcript

1

Chapter One Introduction

This book proposes an analysis of the notion of thinking

(das Denken) in Gottlob Frege and argues that this notion has not

been sufficiently investigated. In fact, the term “thinking” is

disregarded so much as to be forgotten: it does not even deserve

to be mentioned in the index of Michael Dummett’s Frege: Philosophy of

Language and it does not appear in the indexes of the books of

some well-known critics of Dummett such as Hans Sluga or Gregory

Currie.1 This is not surprising given the influence of the

conviction that the study of thinking is psychological and thus

of no interest to logic. It is widely believed that Frege did

not regard human mental processes as philosophically relevant

because of his often declared anti-psychologism.

However, this reading does not explain why Frege says so

much about thinking both in his earlier writings such as

Begriffsschrift (1879) and “On the Scientific Justification for a

Conceptual Notation” (1882), and in his later works such as “Der

Gedanke” (1918-1919) and “Sources of Knowledge of Mathematics and

the Mathematical Natural Sciences” (1924-1925). As a matter of

fact, Frege devoted much attention to human mental processes and

2

to their important role in grasping thoughts and in the

construction of an objective science. Focusing on what he says

about thinking provides insight into his views on the roles of

language in expressing thoughts and in fostering the development

of human knowledge. The main goal of this work is to fill the

gap that most secondary literature on Frege has left open by not

paying close enough attention to what Frege says about thinking.

In this book we provide numerous quotes from Frege’s works,

which should convince even the most skeptical critics that Frege

did indeed pay attention to thinking and had some important

things to say about it. Our hope is that this book will convince

these critics that our effort has been worthwhile.

Frege and the Origin of Analytic Philosophy

The quantity and breadth of scholarship on Frege is

remarkable and credit must be given to Dummett’s extensive study

of Frege’s writings for stimulating such widespread interest in

the work of this German mathematician, logician and philosopher.

Dummett’s Frege: Philosophy of Language2 has inspired heated debates

and provoked the reactions of many.3 According to Dummett, Frege

3

rebels against the Cartesian tradition, which takes epistemology

to be the fundamental branch of philosophy, in order to establish

a new analytic tradition where “the first task, in any

philosophical inquiry, is the analysis of meanings.”4 Our main

goal is to bring to light some concerns of Frege’s which so far

have not been given sufficient attention, namely his concern with

different types of thinking, his interest in epistemological

matters, and his views on the relationship between language and

thinking and language and thought, respectively.

The above three themes are worth discussing not only to

obtain a more complete and accurate interpretation of Frege’s

views, but also to assess one of Dummett’s most intriguing

claims, i.e., the tracking of the origin of analytic philosophy

to Frege. In several of his writings, Dummett argues that Frege

was the initiator of analytic philosophy and of the so called

linguistic turn.5 According to Dummett, Frege generated a shift

from a mostly epistemological or Cartesian focus on the

philosophy of thinking, understood as an inquiry concerning the

mental processes of human beings, which is connected with the

philosophy of mind and which is deeply affected by psychological

4

considerations, to the philosophy of thought.6 Frege referred to

the philosophy of thought as ‘logic’ and characterized it by the

concern with “the question what it is to have a thought, and with

the structure of thoughts and their components: what it is for a

thought to be about an object of one or another kind, what it is

to grasp a concept and how a concept can be a component of a

thought. … the philosophy of thought could not emerge as a

distinguishable sector of the subject until it had been

disentangled from the general philosophy of mind.”7 Dummett is

not the first to ascribe to Frege a central role in such an

important theoretical development as the birth of analytic

philosophy. In the Preface to Our Knowledge of the External World,

i.e., a set of lectures published in 1914, Bertrand Russell

claims that “the first complete example” of analytic philosophy,

which he describes as “the logic-analytic method in philosophy,”

“is to be found in the writings of Frege.”8 Thus, Russell would

have agreed with Dummett on Frege’s merit as the initiator of

analytic philosophy. For Russell, Frege is the initiator of the

“logic-analytic method” that relies on the formal features of

reasoning; Russell regarded Wittgenstein, and not Frege, as the

5

initiator of the linguistic turn in philosophy. To properly

understand and evaluate Dummett’s historical reconstruction –

possibly the claim of Dummett’s that has generated widest

controversy9 – we need to consider more closely how Dummett

defines the distinctive features of analytic philosophy and the

philosophy of thought.

In Origins of Analytical Philosophy, Dummett maintains that “what

distinguishes analytical philosophy, in its diverse

manifestations, from other schools is the belief, first, that a

philosophical account of thought can be attained through a

philosophical account of language, and, secondly, that a

comprehensive account can only be so attained.”10 A combined

statement of these same theses which is dubbed “the fundamental

axiom of analytical philosophy,” is stated as the claim that “the

only route to the analysis of thought goes through the analysis

of language.”11 Analogous statements of these theses appear as

the claim that “the analysis of thought both can and must go via

the analysis of its linguistic expression” or as the claim of

“the priority of language over thought in order of

explanation.”12 We take all these formulations of the axiom of

6

analytic philosophy to assert that a core feature of analytic

philosophy is the acceptance of the thesis that a philosophical

account of language is both necessary and sufficient to provide a

philosophical account of thought. In other words, in analytic

philosophy, an account of language is the only way to obtain a

‘comprehensive’ account of thought.

In reading Dummett’s theses, Gérard Bornet stresses the

independence of the account of language and of the account of

thought as crucial in order to understand Dummett’s claim

concerning the linguistic turn at the origin of analytic

philosophy; Bornet also argues that, if we follow Dummett’s

criterion of linking the birth of analytic philosophy to the so

called ‘linguistic turn,’ then we should regard George Boole as

the true initiator of analytic philosophy whereas Frege merely

developed the “technical apparatus” to support the linguistic

turn.13 We do not enter into this last aspect of the debate

concerning the origin of analytic philosophy and we devote a more

extended discussion to Boole’s philosophical views in the next

chapter. We only note that Dummett’s theses as stated in his

1993 book and the comments that directly follow their statement

7

do not suggest a stress on the independence of the two accounts

but rather on their tight interconnection; for Dummett cites

Gareth Evans’ “posthumous book [1982], which essays an account,

independent of language, of what it is to think about an object”

as almost making Evans “no longer an analytic philosopher”

although he still belongs to this tradition only because he

appeals “to certain writers [i.e., Russell, Moore, and Frege]

rather than to certain others.”14 Thus, Bornet seems to be wrong

in ascribing to Dummett the assumption of independence between

the accounts of language and thought: for Dummett, it is exactly

the assumption of their inextricable dependence that

characterized analytic philosophy, its ancestors as well as its

current practitioners. Yet, there is also something intuitively

right in Bornet’s remark on the need for some independence of the

account of language and the account of thought since if they were

not in some way distinct, neither one could provide any insight

into the other. At the end, we believe that our statement of

Dummett’s theses captures Dummett’s position more accurately than

Bornet’s assumption of the independence of thought and language

does.

8

In Origins of Analytical Philosophy, Dummett famously claims that

Frege was “the grandfather of analytical philosophy.”15 The main

motivation for tracing back to Frege the origin of analytic

philosophy did not change significantly for Dummett over time,

although the Origins description of analytic philosophy is more

broadly and rigorously characterized. Yet, Dummett never claims

that Frege explicitly stated the above theses,16 for he is well

aware that Frege often claimed that the subject matter of his

work focused on thoughts, not on sentences,17 and described his

work as a struggle against language.18 Of course, ‘struggling

against language’ may involve a critical reflection on language,

which is at the core of Dummett’s definition of analytic

philosophy. Ludwig Wittgenstein and Gilbert Ryle were often

‘struggling against language’ in their philosophical reflections

but they are usually regarded as analytic philosophers. Yet,

Frege is also critical of the problems ordinary language creates

for logical thinking. So, on what grounds does Dummett retrace

the birth of analytic philosophy to him?

Dummett’s linking of analytic philosophy to Frege is

complex. We have identified three main reasons for Dummett’s

9

claim. First, in Dummett’s view, Frege’s philosophy is

characterized by the above ‘axiom of analytical philosophy.’ We

indirectly discuss this claim especially in chapter two, which is

devoted to Frege’s anti-psychologism, and chapter five, in which

we argue that Frege’s attitude toward language and its relation

to thinking is more nuanced than the above two theses suggest.

Second, in Dummett’s reading, Frege’s work was at the origin of

analytic philosophy because Frege had very limited interest in

epistemological concerns and thus abandoned the historical

philosophical focus on epistemology or the philosophy of thinking

in favor of a philosophy only focused on thought. Others have

already called in question this claim of Dummett’s and pointed

out that, at least with regard to the realm of mathematical and

logical cognition, Frege was deeply aware of, and wrestled with,

core epistemological issues, such as the grasping of abstract

entities.19 In chapter four we provide evidence that Frege

wrestled with some core epistemological issues, that still

dominate debate in contemporary research, and that he had some

novel ideas about them. Finally, one of Dummett’s main reasons

for linking Frege’s philosophical views to the origin of analytic

10

philosophy is Frege’s stern separation of philosophy and

psychology and his imperative to disallow the use of this latter

for any normative or philosophical reflection. It would be

foolhardy to deny that Frege wrote many critical comments on the

appeal to psychology in inquiries on the justification of

mathematical or logical truths. Yet he took human thinking

seriously; he wrote about it more extensively than it is usually

acknowledged; he distinguished thinking from thoughts, he pointed

out the occurrence of distinct forms of thinking, and reflected

on the relationship between thinking and language pretty much

throughout his whole writing career. We bring new attention to

this theme in order to better circumscribe the features of

Frege’s psychologism and to show how it was grounded in a complex

view of different types of human thinking. This discussion is

developed mostly in chapters two and three.

The analysis of language might plausibly be the only way to

attain the analysis of the content of propositions, but it is

much less plausible to say that it is the only way to attain an

analysis of the process of thinking or of the objects of

thinking; unless, of course, some arguable assumptions are made,

11

e.g., that there cannot be any thinking without language. In the

fifth chapter, we show that Frege discussed these very questions

and believes that language plays a role in fostering thinking.

He does not exactly claim that an analysis of language is a

necessary tool for an analysis of thinking but language is said

by him to be a necessary tool for a certain type of thinking,

namely conceptual thinking as human beings carry it out.

The Scope and Structure of This Book.

We cannot claim that Frege was interested in the mental

process of thinking without discussing the objection that our

main thesis conflicts with his deeply seated anti-psychologism.

This is what we do in the second chapter, in which we review

different understandings of the notion of psychologism and argue

that we do not need to deny Frege’s anti-psychologism. The

discussion in our third chapter focuses on Frege’s three distinct

notions of thinking; in particular, we claim that he held that

there is one form of thinking that can grasps thoughts and that

is not the subjective mental process whose content are ideas, but

a process of thinking that, although it cannot be considered

12

either true or false as no act of thinking can, yet has a deep

connection with truth. In this chapter, we present our main

argument in support of the claim that Frege’s belief in the

possibility of an objective human science can be granted only if

we allow for a notion of thinking that is neither merely

psychological nor merely logical. We call this a type of

logical-psychological thinking that aspires to emulate logical or

pure thinking and to transcend psychological thinking, but that

does not equate or collapse in either one of them. In some

passages Frege indicates that strictly speaking we can never be

sure that we grasp the same meaning, the same definition or the

same thoughts and that instead we have to somehow ‘guess’ what

others have in mind. 20 These passages could be taken to imply

that thinking is wholly and only subjective and that there cannot

be any objective component in human thinking. However, Frege’s

trust in a common system of science and in a shared wealth of

thoughts among humans would be utterly unfathomable if there were

no form of thinking that takes us beyond the thoroughly

subjective world of ideas. We devote the fourth chapter to

arguing that Frege’s interest in thinking is supported by the

13

central role that thinking plays in grasping thoughts and in thus

connecting the subjective world of ideas to the objective world

of thoughts. Finally, in the fifth chapter, we argue that

language plays an epistemic role for Frege both in its necessary

role for thinking and in its representational role for the

expression of thoughts.

Some of the most influential scholars of Frege’s work, such

as Dummett, Sluga, and Carl have discussed the notion of thinking

in connection with the historical context in which Frege

developed his philosophical views on logic and especially his

anti-psychologism, namely in scholarly discussion of historical

figures such as Wilhelm Wundt, Hermann Lotze, or Boole, who are

credited for having influenced Frege’s philosophy by providing a

foil for his critique of psychologism. We believe that Frege’s

discussion on thinking is deeply influenced by these thinkers’

concerns; even if he ended up with positions quite different from

theirs, keeping in mind their preoccupations and problems helps

to bring to light the similarity in Frege’s treatment of thinking

in his own discussion.

14

We are not alone in claiming that Frege paid attention to

epistemically significant notions such as thinking. Wolfgang

Carl’s Frege’s Theory of Sense and Reference Its Origins and Scope remains a

lone work with whose perspective we are very sympathetic. Our

reading of Frege owes much to Carl’s reading. Even if we do not

agree on everything Carl wrote, we share his appreciation of

Frege’s interest in the process of human thinking, but our

analysis of Frege’s notion of thinking goes further than Carl’s.

Among the works published in English so far, there has not been

any discussion devoted only to the notion of thinking and to the

role it plays in Frege’s views on the laws of logic, on

objectivity, science and human knowledge;21 furthermore, we

identify different types of thinking in Frege’s discussion and

point out that thinking is a central player in his defense of the

possibility of objective knowledge. Carl seems to be the only

scholar reading some passages in Frege as we do; since his work

is rarely mentioned in the vast collection of secondary

literature on Frege and seems to have been less influential than

Dummett’s, we would like to reiterate and support with new

evidence some points originally made for the first time by Carl.

15

We hope that a side effect of our discussion will be a broader

acknowledgment of Carl’s unique contribution to the

interpretation of Frege’s thought.

As it will be apparent from the very next chapter, we cite

extensively from Frege’s writings.22 This practice seems to be

necessary to anyone who wants to argue that an author had an

interest in a topic that is rarely associated with such an

author’s philosophy. We believe that these extensive quotations

from Frege’s writings enrich and strengthen rather than interrupt

our discussion, although it may not be a dominant practice in the

secondary literature on Frege; many authors provide overviews of

Frege’s views based on his writings but not directly or

explicitly connected with specific passages. In our citations

from Frege’s writings, at times we cite from works that were

composed at different times in his career. We believe that this

is a legitimate practice in Frege’s case, because there is

remarkable continuity on some major themes in his thought. We

are not alone in thinking this: Dummett stresses a certain

consistency in Frege’s work throughout his life. In contrast to

thinkers such as Russell or Wittgenstein, “Frege’s work can be

16

treated as a unity.”23 Moreover, “views expressed in the mature

period must be taken as having more weight than earlier ones with

which they conflict, and later formulations of old views as

having more weight than the earlier formulations;” exactly

because “Frege worked so single-mindedly at the perfection of his

theories, every change ... must be regarded as fully

deliberate.”24 According to Dummett, the main mistake that can

be made is “to interpret what he said in his mature period in the

light of his earlier writings”25 for “it is unhistorical to read

back into Frege ideas which originated only with his

successors.”26 The majority of Frege’s writings supports the

claim that his views on some central matters changed very little

during his life time. Dummett’s principles of exegesis laid out

above seem highly sensible to us and we strive to abide by them

in our discussion. Accordingly, we will make notice of internal

developments in Frege’s views only when appropriate.

This is not a book in the History of Philosophy or in the

History of Analytic Philosophy; its approach is not historical,

we do not look at all that Frege wrote and we do not pay much

attention to the targets of his views with the lone exception of

17

next chapter’s discussion of Boole’s thought. We focus on the

notion of thinking, because Frege’s comments on thinking are

interesting and salient, and we attempt to bring attention to

them as they have not been often mentioned or discussed. We do

not address directly the question of what is analytic philosophy

or who should be recognized as its initiator although we realize

that, by bringing to light Frege’s views on thinking, we may

indirectly affect the plausibility of attributing a linguistic

turn to his philosophical approach. This is a book on Frege’s

philosophy that touches on some features of analytic philosophy;

it is not a book on analytic philosophy that addresses some

aspects of his philosophy.

We do not look at all secondary literature on Frege: it

would be pretentious to try to do so. It is puzzling that so

much secondary literature is produced on the thought of a writer

whose philosophical work has never been so far reaching or

theoretically rich as René Descartes’s or Immanuel Kant’s. It is

indeed surprising that so much critical work is published on

Frege, since he never dealt explicitly or systematically with

tripartite philosophical issues such as moral values, causation,

18

or the nature of reality. The rich production of secondary

literature on Frege’s views suggests that the influence of a

philosopher’s thought should be measured on the basis not only of

what they have written but also of the works that they have

inspired. Frege’s writings have had a much broader effect than

could be expected; Wittgenstein’s thought is another excellent

example of this phenomenon. Our book aims at enriching the

secondary literature on Frege in an area not broadly discussed.

Our focus is on Frege’s views rather than on the plurality of

interpretations that they have generated.

Some may object to the fact that we often discuss Dummett’s

interpretation of Frege’s philosophy and that Dummett’s work is

often the foil against which we characterize our positions. This

may seem an outdated exercise since Dummett’s work has already

been widely criticized. Despite our deep disagreement with some

core points of Dummett’s interpretation of Frege, we think that

his work still provides the best developed, encompassing,

systematic, and articulated effort to reconstruct Frege’s

thought. This is why Dummett is still our main interlocutor in

19

contrast to other more recent and not yet as influential

scholars.

It may also surprise some scholars that we discuss Frege’s

views on thinking independently from an analysis of the whole of

his logic or his views on sense and reference, hence in isolation

from Frege’s logicist project and his philosophy of language.

This will be particularly surprising for scholars who link

Frege’s epistemological views exclusively to his logicist

concerns. We acknowledge that we find it difficult to determine

whether Frege was first interested in the logicist project and

then in thinking or vice versa. It is however a fact that when

the logicist project fails, because of Russell’s discovery of the

contradiction in Frege’s system, Frege does not abandon his

reflections on thinking, but rather continues to develop them

with a clearer epistemological focus rather than merely in

connection with the foundation of logic and mathematics. Frege’s

thinking - if we are successful in showing that there is one such

notion - plays a role in his epistemological views, namely on his

views concerning the grasping of all thoughts. In chapter four,

we argue that, even if Frege’s interest in epistemological issues

20

originally ensued from his logicist project, he was interested in

such issues for their own sake and, interestingly enough, some of

these issues are still alive in contemporary epistemological

debates.

Since the notion of thinking is usually ignored in

discussions of Frege’s philosophy in favor of widespread

attention to the notion of thought (der Gedanke), whenever

possible we discuss thinking in its relation to thoughts.

Thoughts are claimed to play central roles in Frege’s views on

logic, semantics, philosophy of mathematics, and ontology.

Thinking on the other side is centrally mentioned mostly in

discussion of Frege’s anti-psychologism. We do not claim that

thinking replaces the notion of thought or that it plays an

analogously crucial notion as thoughts play in Frege’s logic,

philosophy of mathematics, or semantics. Our aim is not to

attack this widely shared thought-centered reading of Frege;

instead we claim that the current mainstream interpretation of

his work is incomplete because of its neglect of Frege’s many

comments on thinking and thus needs to be integrated by an

interpretation of the role of thinking in his philosophical views

21

on logic, knowledge and language. Indeed, since Frege’s thinking

is never mentioned in connection with some of the major topics of

discussion in his philosophy, it will be no surprise that our

book will only marginally deal with such major topics; we will

not talk about Frege’s logical and symbolic innovations, or about

his seminal distinction between sense and reference, about his

philosophy of mathematics or about his more or less contested

role in the history of analytic philosophy. Many valuable books

have already been written on these topics, but no book has yet

discussed Frege’s notion of thinking in connection to his

philosophy of logic, his epistemology, his views on language, or

the relationship between Frege’s anti-psychologism and Boole’s

alleged psychologism. Perhaps what we say about Frege’s notion

of thinking in connection with these subjects should lead to a

reconsideration of the place of his views in the development of

20th century analytic philosophy, but this is not a topic we can

discuss in earnest in this book.

Finally, it will be clear that we find Frege’s thought

interesting and stimulating; so do many others scholars, witness

the breadth and richness of the secondary literature on Frege.

22

Yet, working on an author does not mean idealizing his views or

accepting them in their entirety. Frege left many questions

unanswered or only partially answered; some will emerge from our

discussion. The fact that we devote time and effort to bringing

to light a side of his views that is usually not discussed does

not mean that we find Frege’s views in general, and in particular

on thinking, perfectly coherent or flawless; neither do we

implicitly believe that his views are always better than the

views of other thinkers we do not discuss. Our goal is to bring

to light something new, i.e., an aspect of his thought that so

far has not been given sufficient attention.

Das Denken and der Gedanke

One reason that might have led to the under-evaluation of

the role of thinking in Frege’s views is the fact that many,

although certainly not all, readers of Frege rely on the English

translations of his main works, which frequently obscure the fact

that he used two distinct German terms for thinking and thoughts,

i.e., das Denken and der Gedanke.

23

The practice of translating ‘das Denken’ as ‘thought’ has

greatly diminished the number of passages in which it is apparent

that Frege discusses thinking and has given unwarranted support

to the claim that he promoted the philosophy of thought in

contrast to the philosophy of thinking.27 More significantly, it

has obscured the presence in Frege of a notion of thinking that

is not of a merely psychological nature. In this book, we have

routinely amended the official translations of Frege, by

replacing ‘thought’ with ‘thinking’ every time in German Frege

used ‘das Denken’ and limited the use of ‘thought’ to those places

where ‘der Gedanke’ occurs in German. Since it is our goal both to

provide textual evidence that Frege discussed das Denken,

i.e.,‘thinking,’ and to reflect his use of das Denken and der

Gedanke more accurately, we italicize the word ‘thinking’ every

time we use it instead of ‘thought’ in variance with standard

translations of his writings.28

In the late 1890’s and in the last years of his life, Frege

explicitly acknowledged a distinction between the notion of

thinking, das Denken, and the notion of thought, or der Gedanke.

However, he did not contrast das Denken and der Gedanke throughout

24

the whole development of his career. Begriffsschrift and the articles

written shortly thereafter, in which Frege defends his conceptual

notation, show that he was interested in thinking before he

developed his notion of thought or der Gedanke. It makes thus

sense to infer that the notion of thinking is philosophically

interesting for Frege and autonomous from the notion of thought,

although after 1892 and the writing of “On Sense and Reference,”

when he did develop his notion of der Gedanke as an objective

abstract entity, this latter notion might have provided Frege

with an appropriate term of contrast for das Denken or the mental

process of thinking.29

Frege wanted to avoid any confusion between thoughts, i.e.,

the content of propositions, and thinking, i.e., the mental

process.30 Moreover, he was deeply aware of the need for a

consistent use of the words der Gedanke and das Denken to denote

thoughts and thinking, respectively:

What if it is objected that I am attaching to the word

‘thought’ [“Gedanke”] a sense that it does not ordinarily

have, and that other people understand by it an act of

thinking [eine Tat des Denkens], which is obviously private

25

and mental? Well, the important thing is that I remain true

to my way of using it; whether this agrees with the ordinary

use is of less importance. It may well be the case that

people sometimes understand by the word ‘thought’ an act of

thinking – in any case this is not always so* – and such an

act cannot be true.31

Here Frege provides an almost stipulative definition of der

Gedanke and declares his intention never to use this term to

denote an act of thinking, which he instead denotes with the term

das Denken. The awareness of the need to keep the use of these

two terms clearly distinct might have increased after the

completion of the first volume of Grundgesetze where Frege

explicitly acknowledges that what he used to call “judgeable

content,” for example in Begriffsschrift, has now split into what he

now calls thought and truth-value. He also plans on being

consistent in using these terms. From this passage, we can glean

that he believed that the use of der Gedanke by other people

created the same problem that the English word “thought” creates

on the part of English speakers: sometimes denoting the content

of propositions and sometimes denoting the mental process of

26

thinking. At the end of the passage, Frege restates his well-

known thesis that thoughts and thinking have different properties

since truth appropriately belongs to thoughts, but not to acts of

thinking.

Most of the times, in translations of Frege’s writings,

there is no ambiguity between thoughts and thinking. Take for

example the following passage in which Frege is clearly talking

about thoughts as propositions: “Let Ω be a group of true

thoughts. Let a thought G follow from one or several of the

thoughts of this group by means of a logical inference such that

apart from the laws of logic, no proposition not belonging to Ω

is used. Let us now form a new group of thoughts by adding the

thought G to the group …”32 In the German original of the passage

just quoted, Frege uses the word der Gedanke throughout, and the

standard translation correctly uses the word “thought(s).” In

contrast, in the German original of the following passage, Frege

uses only das Denken and the standard translation correctly uses

“thinking” throughout: “But isn’t thinking a kind of speaking?

How is it possible for thinking to be engaged in a struggle with

speaking? Wouldn’t that be a struggle in which thinking was at

27

war with itself? Doesn’t this spell the end to the possibility

of thinking?”33

However, sometimes the duplicity of meaning of the English

word “thought” introduces an ambiguity in the translation, which

is not present in the original text. At the beginning of the

last paragraph in “What is a Function?”, Frege writes, “Das

Streben nach Kürze hat viele ungenaue Ausdrücke in die

mathematische Sprache eingefürt, und diese haben rüchwirkend die

Gedanken getrübt and fehlerhafte Definition zuwege gebracht.”34

The standard translation reads, “The endeavour to be brief has

introduced many inexact expressions into mathematical language,

and these have reacted by obscuring thought and producing faulty

definitions.”35 Die Gedanken in the original is correctly

translated with “thought” and not “thinking.” However, in

German, die Gedanken is plural, while in the English translation

“thought” is singular and thus ambiguous, possibly denoting the

content of a proposition or the process of thinking. The result

is that it is possible to read this passage as one in which Frege

is charging the drive for brevity in mathematical language of

having fostered the adoption of imprecise expressions, which are

28

responsible for clouding the process of thinking and generating

faulty definitions. Yet, if Frege is as careful as he claims to

be about the usage of der Gedanke and das Denken, this cannot be the

correct meaning of this sentence. Instead, the whole paragraph

concerns the obscurity and falsehood of thoughts or propositions

generated by a faulty process of definition. A more literal

translation would read, “The endeavour to be brief has introduced

many inexact expressions into mathematical language, and these

have reacted by obscuring [the] thoughts {die Gedanken, or the

contents of propositions} and producing faulty definitions.” It

is the obscurity of the thoughts, not the clouding of the process

of thinking that is a consequence of the excessive brevity of

definitions. What follows this passage renders explicit that

Frege is indeed talking about propositions (die Gedanken) rather

than of thinking (das Denken), for he continues, “Mathematics

ought properly to be a model of logical clarity. In actual fact

there are perhaps no scientific works where you will find more

wrong expressions, and consequently wrong thoughts, than in

mathematical ones.” The terms Frege uses here parallel those he

uses in the first sentence: Ausdrüche and Gedanken, “expressions”

29

and “thoughts:” both are found in mathematical works, both are

labeled as schiefe, i.e., as false, defective, wrong.

Problems arising from this type of ambiguities persist in

recently published research and even among careful scholars who

do not trust the official English translations of Frege’s

writings to express his views faithfully.36 The significance of

these misinterpretations of Frege’s views on thinking and

thoughts may be debatable, but this lack of precision in keeping

separate thoughts and thinking clearly does not match the care

with which Frege distinguished between der Gedanke and das Denken.

Finally, even philosophers who see the occurrences of these two

German terms do not ascribe to them serious philosophical

significance.

Although we cannot point out all the passages we have found

where das Denken has been translated with ‘thought’ and not

‘thinking,’ it is worth mentioning this other passage from

Grundgesetze because in the most recent translation of it, Frege’s

choice of terms has been fortunately more carefully heeded.

Montgomery Furth translated this passage as follows: “[w]e cannot

reject this law – of Identity, for example; we must acknowledge

30

it unless we wish to reduce our thought {unser Denken} to

confusion and finally renounce all judgment whatever.”37 In

Furth’s translation, the singular “thought” suggests the correct

notion of “thinking.” In the new complete translation of

Grundgesetze this passage more explicitly reads: “we cannot

discard this law – of identity, for example – but have to

acknowledge it if we do not want to lead our thinking into

confusion and in the end abandon judgment altogether.”38

The unfortunate use of the English word ‘thought’ to

translate both das Denken and der Gedanke means that if we take into

account only the occurrences of the term “thinking” in the

English translations of Frege, it does seem indeed that he wrote

very little about the mental process of thinking. The problem is

that in the classic English translations of Frege’s writings the

term “thinking” was used with rare exceptions only when it was

obvious that Frege was talking about the psychological and

subjective process of thinking; this was of course an accurate

translation of das Denken because he did use this term to denote

the subjective actual mental processes of thinking and we know

that he believed that these subjective mental processes were of

31

no interest to logic. However, there are also passages in which

Frege used das Denken when he was not discussing specific

individual mental processes, but thinking as a process with

philosophical and logical relevance. This is the main thesis we

defend in this book.

One further note on the translation of das Denken: in several

passages Frege uses the expression “das wirkliche Denken,” which is

often translated in English as “thinking as it actually occurs.”

The German original expression, which can be literally rendered

as “the actual thinking,” leads to an implicit contrast with “das

reine Denken,” or “the pure thinking,” which appears for example –

and quite significantly - in the subtitle of the Begriffsschrift.

This contrast is important to reach a thorough understanding of

Frege’s views on thinking. For Frege, thinking is not always the

subject matter of psychology: specific subjective mental

processes of thinking, or instances of actual thinking, are the

concern of psychology. However, there is also another type of

thinking, which Frege calls pure thinking {reine Denken} and which

is the proper object of the logicians’ and philosophers’

reflection. Thus, translating “das wirkliche Denken” as “actual

32

thinking” in contrast with “das reine Denken” or “pure thinking”

suggests the possibility of different types of thinking, which

the expression “thinking as it actually happens” does not

suggest. We will thus adapt our translations of Frege’s passages

to this further stipulation.

1. Hans Sluga, Gottlob Frege (London: Routledge, 1980); Gregory Currie,

Frege, An Introduction to His Philosophy (Brighton: The Harvester Press, 1982).

Edward Kanterian’s recently published introduction to Frege

uncharacteristically lists in the index “thinking” together with

“thought.” See Kanterian, Frege A Guide for the Perplexed (London and New

York: Continuum, 2012), 248. Although we argue that keeping

“thinking” and “thought” carefully distinct is crucial for a correct

understanding of Frege’s views, it is encouraging to see that Frege’s

“thinking” (no pun intended) is occasionally noticed.

2. Michael Dummett, Frege: Philosophy of Language (London: Duckworth,

1973).

3. See among others Sluga, Frege; Currie, Frege; Wolfgang Carl, Frege’s

Theory of Sense and Reference (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press,

1994).

4. Dummett, Frege: Philosophy of Language, 667.

5. Dummett, Frege: Philosophy of Language, 665-684; The Interpretation of Frege’s

Philosophy (London: Duckworth, 1981a), 39; “Introduction” to the

Italian Edition of Frege, G., Logical Investigations (Milan: Guerini,

1988), 25-37, 35; Origins of Analytical Philosophy (London: Duckworth, 1993),

4-14, 22, 26, 127-128.

6. It may be claimed that Dummett’s representation of the history of

philosophy from Descartes to Frege is a mere caricature of the

development of philosophy in that period. We concede this point, but

a more in depth discussion of the views of Descartes is not our focus

here.

7. Dummett, Origins, 129.

8. See Russell, Our Knowledge of the External World (London: Allen & Unwin,

1926),7.

9. See Sluga, “Frege and the Rise of Analytical Philosophy,” Inquiry

18 (1975): 471-87; “Frege as a Rationalist,” in Studien zu Frege, Volume

I, Logik und Philosophie der Mathematik, ed. Matthias Schirn, Problemata,

no. 42 (Stuttgart and Bad Cannstatt: Frommann-Holzboog 1976), 27-47;

“Frege’s Alleged Realism,” Inquiry 20 (1977): 227-42; Frege, 1-6; Stuart

Shanker, “Review of Michael Dummett ‘Frege: Philosophy of language’”

Dialogue 21 (1982): 565-571; Hans-Johann Glock, “Dummett on the Roots

of Analytical Philosophy,” Mind 98 (1989): 646-49; Johannes Brandl,

“Michael Dummett: Ursprünge der analytischen Philosophie. Ubers. von

Joachim Schulte. Frankfurt .M.: Suhrkamp 1988,” Archiv für Geschichte der

Philosophie 73 (1991): 337-344; Herman Philipse, “Husserl and the

Origins of Analytical Philosophy,” European Journal of Philosophy 2, 2

(1994): 165-184. Gideon Makin denies that Frege was primarily

interested in language, see The Metaphysicians of Meaning: Russell and Frege on

Sense and Denotation (London and New York: Routledge, 2000). Some recent

views on the origins of analytic philosophy contrast with Dummett’s

view, see Peter M. S. Hacker, “Analytic Philosophy: Beyond the

Linguistic Turn and Back Again,” in The Analytic Turn: Analysis in Early Analytic

Philosophy and Phenomenology, ed. Michael Beaney (London: Routledge,

2007): 125-141; Peter Hylton, Russell, Idealism, and the Emergence of Analytic

Philosophy (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990); Scott Soames, Philosophical

Analysis in the Twentieth Century, Volume 1 (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University

Press, 2003) and The Analytic Tradition in Philosophy, Vol 1: Founding Giants

(Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2014).

10. Dummett, Origins of Analytic Philosophy, 4. A more rigorous statement is

given in The Interpretation of Frege’s Philosophy, 39: “The basic tenet of

analytical philosophy … may be expressed as being that the philosophy

of thought is to be equated with the philosophy of language: more

exactly, (i) an account of language does not presuppose an account of

thought, (ii) an account of language yields an account of thought,

and (iii) there is no other adequate means by which an account of

thought may be given.”

11. Dummett, Origins, 128.

12. Dummett, Origins, 134, 148.

13. Gérard Bornet, “George Boole’s Linguistic Turn and the Origins of

Analytical Philosophy,” in The British Tradition in 20th Century Philosophy, eds.

Jaakko Hintikka and Klaus Puhl (Vienna:Verlag Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky,

1995), 236-248, 236.

14. Dummett, Origins, 5-6.

15. Dummett, Origins, 14, 26; this claim was previously stated in the

Introduction to the Italian Edition of Frege’s Logische Untersuchungen

(Milano: Guerini, 1988), 35. Notice that in an essay entitled

“Frege’s Place in the History of Philosophy,” published in the 1973

first edition of Frege Philosophy of Language, Dummett states that “Frege

can ... be considered the father of ‘linguistic philosophy,’” where

this latter is understood as ‘all philosophy which sees the key to

the analysis of concepts as consisting in the study of the means of

their expression.’ Whether or not the debate generated by Dummett’s

ascription of the origin of analytic philosophy to Frege was the

factor that caused the demotion from father to grandfather has never,

to our knowledge, been mentioned in print by Dummett.

16. Bornet also points out this fact: “Astonishingly enough, Dummett

has difficulties making Frege look like an analytic philosopher on

his own characterization.” “George Boole’s Linguistic Turn,” 236.

17. “Frege became more and more insistent that thoughts, and not the

sentences that express them, formed his true subject matter.” See

Dummett, Origins, 5. For an example of a passage in which Frege makes

this point, see Frege “Logic in Mathematics,“ in Posthumous Writings,

transl. Peter Long and Roger White (Basil Blackwell, Oxford, 1979),

206.

18. Dummett, Origins, 6. See Frege, Conceptual Notation and Related Articles

(Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1879), 106; “On the Scientific

Justification,” 83-86; “Sources of Knowledge of Mathematics and the

mathematical natural Sciences”, in Posthumous Writings (Basil Blackwell,

Oxford, 1979), 267-274, 270. For a discussion of Frege’s views on

ordinary language, see Andrew Rein, “Frege and Natural Language”

Philosophy 60, No. 234 (1985): 513-524.

19. See especially David Bell, Frege’s Theory of Judgment (Oxford, UK:

Clarendon Press 1979); Carl, Frege’s Theory; Tyler Burge, “Frege on

Knowing the Third Realm,” Mind 101(1992): 633-650; “Frege on Knowing

the Foundation,” Mind 107 (1998): 305-347; “Frege on Apriority,” in

Building on Frege New Essays on Sense,Content, and Concept, eds. Albert Newen et

al. (Stanford: CSLI. 2001), 53-87; Currie, Frege; Graciela De Pierris,

“Frege and Kant on A Priori Knowledge,” Synthese 77 (1988): 285-319;

Richard Eldridge, “Frege’s Realist Theory of Knowledge,” Review of

Metaphysics 35 (1982): 483-508; Gottfried Gabriel, “Frege’s

Epistemology in Disguise,” in Frege: Importance and Legacy, ed. Matthias

Schirn (Hawthorne, New York: de-Gruyter, 1996), 330-346; Bob Hale and

Crispin Wright, eds. The Reason’s Proper Study: essays towards a neo-Fregean

philosophy of mathematics (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2001); Philip Kitcher,

“Frege’s Epistemology,” Philosophical Review 88 (1979): 235-262; Wolfgang

Malzkorn, “How Do We ‘Grasp’ a Thought, Mr. Frege?” in Newen, Building

on Frege,329-344; Mark Amadeus Notturno, Objectivity, Rationality and the Third

Realm (Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff, 1985); Sluga, Gottlob Frege; Joan

Weiner Frege in Perspective (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1990).

20. “In practice ... we do manage to come to an understanding about

the meanings of words. Of course we have to be able to count on a

meeting of minds, on others guessing what we have in mind.” “Logic in

Mathematics,” 207; “[W]e must be able to count on a little good will

and cooperative understanding, even guessing.” “On the Foundations of

Geometry: Second Series.” Translated by Max Black et al. In Collected

Papers on Mathematics, Logic and Philosophy, 293-340 (Oxford: Basil Blackwell,

1984), 300ff.

21. Two exceptions published in German are Markus Stepanians, Frege

und Husserl über Urteilen und Denken (Paderborn: Schöningh 1998) and Wolfgang

Künne, Die Philosophische Logik Gottlob Freges: Ein Kommentar (Frankfurt am Main:

Klostermann 2010).

22. Following a practice now fairly common, in the text we refer to

Begriffsschrift, Grundgesetze, and Grundlagen by their original German

titles. Most of the times we quote from translations of Frege’s

works cited in the endnote and references section. We indicate

explicitly when we modify the translation or provide our translation.

23. Dummett, Origins, 628; Dummett, The Interpretation of Frege’s Philosophy, 6.

24. Dummett, The Interpretation of Frege’s Philosophy, 7.

25. Dummett, The Interpretation of Frege’s Philosophy, 7.

26. Dummett, Frege and Other Philosophers (Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press,

1991), 217. Yet, this is the error that Shanker claims Dummett

committed in Frege and in The Interpretation of Frege’s Philosophy and that is

at the origin of Dummett’s claim that Frege’s philosophy anticipated

the linguistic turn carried out by analytic philosophers; see

Shanker, “Review.”

27. “Frege made a very clear distinction between questions about the

content of thoughts and the meaning of sentences, on the one hand,

and genuinely epistemological questions about, say, the process of

thinking, on the other.” Dummett, Origins, 185. More than ten years

earlier, Dummett also writes, “[T]he agreement of all might be

secured for the adoption, as a neutral designation for that branch of

philosophy which Frege called simply “logic”, of the term ‘the

philosophy of thought’, which, as he would have been the first to

insist, is to be sharply distinguished from a philosophical account

of thinking.” Dummett, The Interpretation of Frege’s Philosophy, 39.

28. In the effort to avoid the ambiguity of using ‘thought’ to

translate both das Denken and der Gedanke in Frege, other authors have

used ‘Thought’ to translate the latter and left ‘thought’ to

translate the former. Although this is a viable solution to the

issue of the ambiguity of the English term ‘thought,’ our proposal

brings to sharper focus the fact that thinking is a mental process.

Because of the importance of psychologism, which we discuss in the

next chapter, we believe our proposal is preferable. See for example

Marcos Barbosa de Oliveira, “Logic and Cognitive Science: Frege’s

Anti-Psychologism,” Manuscrito 17. No. 2 (1994): 77 fn. 10.

29. At the time of Begriffsschrift, Inhalt was the notion closer to what

Frege later called Gedanke. Dummett points out that Frege discussed

der Gedanke before Begriffsschrift and suggests that for this reason he

might have gone back to using this term when he split the notion of

content or Inhalt into thought and truth-value in “On Sense and

Reference.” See Dummett, “Frege’s ‘Kernsätze zur Logik,” Inquiry, 24,

(1981), 447. On the notion of Inhalt in Frege, see also Eva Picardi,

‘On Frege's notion of ‘Inhalt,’’ in Atti del Convegno Internazionale di Storia

della Logica, 307-312.

30. Dummett correctly points out that “Frege was always punctilious

in distinguishing between thinking (das Denken), which is a proper

subject-matter for psychology, and the thought (der Gedanke) that the

subject thinks, which is not.” Dummett, “Preface to the Italian

Edition of Frege. Philosophy of Language” (Casale Monferrato: Marietti,

1983), xii.

31. Frege, “Logic” (1897), in Posthumous Writings, transl. Peter Long

and Roger White (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1979), 135-136. A few pages

earlier, in his outline of this article, Frege states, “[135]

Objection: my use of the word ‘thought’ is out of the ordinary.

[136] Footnote. Dedekind’s way of using it agrees with mine.” The

asterisk in the quote leads to an extended footnote on Richard

Dedekind’s use of the word Gedanke.

32. Frege, “Foundations of Geometry: Second Series,” in Collected Papers

on Mathematics, Logic and Philosophy. Translated by Max Black et al. (Oxford:

Basil Blackwell, 1984), 293-340, 334

33. Frege, “Erkenntnisquellen der Mathematik und der mathematischen

Naturwissenschaften,” 270.

34. Frege, “Was ist eine Funktion?” In Kleine Schriften (Hildesheim:

Georg Olmos Verlagsbüchhanslung, 1967), 273-280, 280.

35. Frege, “What is a Function?” in Collected Papers on Mathematics, Logic and

Philosophy (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1984), 285-292. 292.

36. Kanterian for example explicitly mentions to have “followed the

German originals and substantially diverged from the English

translations listed in his bibliography;” see Kanterian, Frege, 221,

footnote 2. Nonetheless, in his analysis of a well-known passage from

the Preface of Begriffsschrift in which Frege argues for the usefulness of

his conceptual notation as a “tool” for philosophers and for its

ability to free “thought” {den Gedanken, in the original} from that

which only the nature of the linguistic means of expression attaches

to it,” Kanterian interprets Frege’s passage to be about das Denken.

For, according to Kanterian, this Fregean passage: “assumes that all

language may have a pernicious influence on our thinking” and “

presupposes that our thinking can be freed from this influence, detached

at least from that aspect of language which does not faithfully

represent thinking.” See Kanterian, Frege, 43 [our emphasis]. In this

famous passage from the Preface of Begriffsschrift however, Frege was

stressing the problems created by language for the accurate

expression of “thoughts,” as clearly indicated by the occurrence of

Gedanken in the original German text.

37. Frege, The Basic Laws of Aritmetic, 15.

38. Frege, Frege: Basic Laws of Arithmetic, xvii. From the merely cursory

examination of the new complete translation of Grundgesetze that we

have been able to do, it seems to us that in several places the

recent translation heeds more closely to Frege’s deliberate use of

das Denken and der Gedanke than the previous partial translations did.

Accordingly, unless otherwise specified, we usually quote from the

2013 translation of Grundgesetze.


Recommended